Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-qsmjn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-18T19:15:01.048Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

In Defence of Modernity*

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  13 April 2010

Hilliard Aronovitch
Affiliation:
University of Ottawa

Extract

Is the endeavour to probe the meaning of modernity other than a form of self-obsession, a kind of collective and conceptual narcissism, characteristic of the perhaps peculiarly modern preoccupation with abstract notions and inwardness? And whatever the motivation and origin, is the endeavour likely to issue in something better than doubtful or empty pronouncements, true to the extent that they are platitudes and false or obscure for the rest? Encountering the title Modernism as a Philosophical Problem one can imagine a Rortyean reading: modernism a philosophical problem?—and the commentary: well, if you think that, you do have a problem, namely, philosophical pretentiousness and an affliction for foundations, for ultimate principles that, if truly ultimate, are unattainable and also unnecessary. In a different voice, a similar cynicism can be heard, the Lyotardean lament at the announcement of yet another unneeded philosophical meta-narrative, a new, idle tale about history, ideas and development, culminating in grand notions confounded by facts.

Type
Critical Notices/Études critiques
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Philosophical Association 1995

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Notes

1 Pippin classifies Habermas as only a “highly qualified” defender of modernity (p. 15). See Habermas, Jürgen, The Theory of Comunicative Action, Vol. 1, Reason and Rationalization of Society, translated by McCarthy, T. (Boston, MA: Beacon Press, 1984)Google Scholar; The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity, translated by Lawrence, F. (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1987)Google Scholar; “Questions and Counter-questions,” in Habermas and Modernity, edited by Bernstein, Richard J. (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1985).Google ScholarRawls, Regarding, I refer to the original project, that is, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), though later papers, collected now as Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993), involve a shift to which I allude at the end of this essay; also,Google ScholarGellner, Ernest, Postmodernism, Reason, and Religion (London: Routledge, 1992)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

2 Rorty, Richard, Consequences of Pragmatism (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1982), and Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989)Google Scholar; Toulmin, Stephen, Cosmopolis: The Hidden Agenda of Modernity (New York: New York Free Press, 1990)Google Scholar; Taylor, Charles, Sources of the Self (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989), and The Ethics of Authenticity (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1992)Google Scholar.

3 On post-Modernists: Lyotard, Jean-Francois, The Post-Modern Condition: A Report on Knowledge, translated by Bennington, G. and Massumi, B. (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1984); for different readings of Derrida, and specific texts, seeGoogle ScholarEllis, John, Against Deconstruction (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1989) versusGoogle ScholarNorris, Christopher, What's Wrong With Post-modernism (Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1990), chaps. 1,3, 5 and passim; also Bernstein, Habermas and Modernity.Google Scholar

On pre-Modernists: Maclntyre, Alasdair, After Virtue (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1984); also Whose Justice? Which Rationality? (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1988); and Three Rival Versions of Moral Inquiry (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1990);Google ScholarGadamer, Hans-Georg, Truth and Method, translated by Barden, G. and Cumming, J. (London: Sheed and Ward, 1975)Google Scholar; Strauss, Leo, Natural Right and History (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1953)Google Scholar.

4 Pippin discusses Beaudelaire, Flaubert and others to sketch the origins of Modernism. The sensibility of Modernism sought refuge from the routinization and disappointments of modern life in the values of art, culture, sentiment and so forth; Pippin acknowledges the èlitism with which this could be entangled. For other explorations of Modernism, emphasizing its diversity plus its proneness at times to nihilism and political extremism, see Howe, Irving, “The Idea of The Modern,” in Literary Modernism, edited by Howe, Irving (Greenwich, CT: Fawcett, 1967), pp. 25ff., plus essays by Lionel Trilling and others therein;Google ScholarKermode, Frank, “The Modern,” in Modern Essays (London: Collins, Fontana Books, 1971), pp. 3970, esp. p. 61; andGoogle ScholarGalston, William A., Liberal Purposes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991) pp. 5960. Familiarly, post-Modernism sees Modernism as still too tied to modernity, particularly the longing for subjectivity, ultimacy and so forth, and as needing to be supersededCrossRefGoogle Scholar.

5 For modernity beginning with the Renaissance humanists, see Toulmin, , Cos-mopolis, p. 4243, n.2Google Scholar.

6 For Taylor, , see note 2 above, and Hegel and Modern Society (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979); alsoGoogle ScholarAvineri, Shlomo, referenced below. Pippin himself has also authored Hegel's Idealism: The Satisfactions of Self-Consciousness (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1989); and for the period generally,Google ScholarConnolly, William E., Political Theory and Modernity (New York and Oxford: Blackwell, 1988)Google Scholar.

7 Cf. Nehamas, Alexander, Nietzsche: Life as Literature (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1985).Google Scholar

8 On Hedegger's Nazism see Farias, Victor, Heidegger et le Nazisme (Paris: Verdier, 1987);Google ScholarFerry, Luc and Renaut, Alain, Heidegger and Modernity, translated by Philip, F. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990)Google Scholar; Wolin, Richard, The Politics of Being (New York: Columbia Unversity Press, 1993). Richard Rorty fully accepts the facts about Heidegger's Nazi past, and accepts its reflection on the man but not on his philosophy, which stretches the distance between philosophy and practice to the point of incredulity. SeeGoogle ScholarRorty's, review of Farias's book in The New Republic, April 11,1988, pp. 3134 and his further speculations ni “Diary,” London Review of Books, February 8, 1990, p. 21Google Scholar.

9 Avèneri, Shlomo, Hegel's Theory of the Modern State (London: Cambridge University Press, 1972)CrossRefGoogle Scholar;O'Neill, Onora, Constructions of Reason: Explorations of Kant's Practical Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989)Google Scholar.

10 Walzer, Michael, Spheres of Justice (New York: Basic Books, 1983).Google Scholar