Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-wq2xx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-18T07:32:03.175Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Psychologie évolutionniste et théories interdomaines*

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  13 April 2010

Luc Faucher
Affiliation:
Université du Québec à Montréal
Pierre Poirier
Affiliation:
Université du Québec à Montréal

Abstract

Evolutionary psychology presupposes relations between theories of different domains that the two traditional models, reduction and autonomy, cannot properly account for. We aim to construct a model of relations between theories that succeeds where traditional models fail. We show that the multiple realizability argument, on which the autonomist model is thought to rest, is compatible with reductionism and, following Kim, that an autonomist reading of the argument deprives psychology of its scientific status. We therefore opt for a reductionist model compatible with functionalism and multiple realizability, but show that, within evolutionary psychology at least, the very application of the conditions of reduction requires strong interactions between psychology and various other adjacent disciplines. We also show that reduction must be preceded in evolutionary psychology by an “augmentation” of the reduction base, which brings still other disciplines into play. Finally, we present a model of the interaction between disciplines we believe accounts best for these relations and discuss the problems facing this kind of enterprise.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Philosophical Association 2001

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

références bibliographiques

Allen, C. et Bekoff, M. 1995 «Biological Function, Adaptation, and Natural Selection», Philosophy of Science, vol. 62, p. 609622.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Andrews, P. et Stringer, C. 1993 «L'évolution humaine», dans Le livre de la vie, sous la direction de Gould, S. J., Paris, Seuil, p. 218253.Google Scholar
Barkow, J. 1990 «Beyond the DP/DSS Controversy», Ethology and Sociobiology, vol. 11, p. 341351.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barkow, J.Cosmides, L. et Tooby, J. 1992 The Adapted Mind : Evolutionary Psychology and the Generation of Culture, Oxford, Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bechtel, W. 1988 Philosophy of Mind: An Overview for Cognitive Science, Hillsdale, NJ, Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.Google Scholar
Bechtel, W. 1994Biological and Social Constraints on Cognitive Processes : The Need for Dynamical Interactions between Levels of Inquiry», Canadian Journal of Philosophy, volume supplemental 20, p. 133164.Google Scholar
Bechtel, W. et Abrahamsen, A. 1993 «Interfield Connections and Psychology», dans Annals of Theoretical Psychology, sous la direction de Rappard, H., New York, Plenum Press, vol. 9, p. 125139.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bechtel, W. et Richardson, R. 1992 «Emergent Phenomena and Complex Systems», dans Emergence or Reduction? : Essays on the Prospects of Nonreductive Physicalism, sous la direction d' Beckermann, A.Flohr, H. et Kim, J.Berlin, Walter de Gruyter, p. 257288.Google Scholar
Bickle, J. 1998 Psychoneural Reduction, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press.Google Scholar
Boyd, R. 1999 «Kinds, Complexity and Multiple Realization», Philosophical Studies, vol. 95, p. 6798.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buss, D. M. 1999 Evolutionary Psychology : The New Science of the Mind, Boston, Allyn and Bacon.Google Scholar
Buss, D. M.Haselton, G.Shackelford, T. K.Bleske, A. L. et Wakefield, J. C. 1998 «Adaptations, Exaptations, and Spandrels», American Psychologist, vol. 53, nº 5, p. 533548.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Churchland, P. S. 1986 Neurophilosophy, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press.Google Scholar
Clark, A. 1998 «Embodiment and the Philosophy of Mind», dans Current Issues in Philosophy of Mind, supplement de Philosophy, nº 43, sous la direction d'O'Hear, A., Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, p. 533548.Google Scholar
Coppens, Y. 1994 «Une histoire de l'origine des hominidés», Pour la science, nê 201 (juillet), p. 6471.Google Scholar
Cosmides, L. et Tooby, J. 1987 «From Evolution to Behavior : Evolutionary Psychology as the Missing Link», dans The Latest on the Best, sous la direction de Dupre, J., Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, p. 278306.Google Scholar
Cosmides, L. et Tooby, J. 1994a «Beyond Intuition and Instinct Blindness : Toward an Evolutionary Rigourous Cognitive Science», Cognition, vol. 50, p. 4177.Google Scholar
Cosmides, L. et Tooby, J. 1994b «Origins of Domain Specificity : The Evolution of Functional Organization«, dans Mapping the Mind, sous la direction de Gelman, S. et Hirshfield, L.Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, p. 85116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cosmides, L. et Tooby, J. 1995 «From Function to Structure : The Role of Evolutionary Biology and Computational Theories in Cognitive Neuroscience», dans The Cognitive Neurosciences, sous la direction de Gazzaniga, M., Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, p. 11991210.Google Scholar
Cosmides, L. et Tooby, J. 1997 «The Modular Nature of Human Intelligenc», dans The Origin and Evolution of Intelligence, sous la direction d'Scheibel, A. B. et Schoff, J. W., Boston, Jones and Bartlett Publishers, p. 71101.Google Scholar
Cosmides, L.Tooby, J. et Barkow, J. 1992 «Introduction : Evolutionary Psychology and Conceptual Integration », dans Barkow, Cosmides et Tooby, 1992, p. 315.Google Scholar
Cummins, R. 1983 «Functional Analysis», The Journal of Philosophy, vol. 72, p. 741764.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cummins, R. 1983 The Nature of Psychological Explanation, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press.Google Scholar
Darden, L. et Maull, N. 1977 «Interfield Theory», Philosophy of Science, vol. 44, p. 4364.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dufour, J. P. 1995 «Abel secoue l'arbre généalogique de l'humanité», Le Devoir, mercredi 22 novembre, p. B4.Google Scholar
Enc, B. 1983 «In Defense of the Identity Theory», The Journal of Philosophy, vol. 80, p. 279298.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. 1974 «Special Sciences (or: The Disunity of Science as a Working Hypothesis)», Synthese, vol. 28, p. 97115; trad, de P. Jacob sous le titre «Les sciences particulieres (l'absence d'unite de la science : une hypothese de travail)», dans De Vienne à Cambridge, sous la direction de P. Jacob, Paris, Gallimard, 1980, p. 379–400.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. 1983 The Modularity of Mind, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. 1998 In Critical Condition, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. 2000 The Mind Doesn't Work that Way, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gigerenzer, G.Todd, P. et le ABC Group 1999 Simple Heuristics that Make Us Smart, Oxford, Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Godfrey-Smith, P. 1993 «Functions : Consensus without Unity», Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, vol. 74, p. 196208.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Godfrey-Smith, P. 1994 «A Modern History Theory of Functions»,Noûs.y, vol. 28, p. 344362.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldsmith, T. H. 1990 «Optimization, Constraint, and History in the Evolution of Eyes», The Quarterly Review of Biology, vol. 65, p. 281322.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gould, J. et Marler, P. 1987 «Learning by Instinct», Scientific American, nº 256, p. 7485.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gould, S. J. et Lewontin, R. 1984 «The Spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm : A Critique of the Adaptationist Programme», dans Conceptual Issues in Evolutionary Biology, sous la direction de Sober, E., Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, p. 252270.Google Scholar
Griffiths, P. E. 1992 «Adaptative Explanation and the Concept of a Vestige», dans Trees of Life : Essays in Philosophy of Biology, sous la direction de Griffiths, P. E.Kluwer, DordrechtAcademic Publishers, p. 111131.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffiths, P. E. 1993 «Functional Analysis and Proper Functions», British Journal of Philosophy of Science, vol. 44, p. 409422.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffiths, P. E. 1994 «Cladistic Classification and Functional Explanation», Philosophy of Science, vol. 61, p. 206227.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffiths, P. E. 1996a «Darwinism, Process Structuralism, and Natural Kinds», Philosophy of Science, vol. 63, Proceedings, p. S1-S9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffiths, P. E. 1996b «The Historical Turn in the Study of Adaptation», British Journal of Philosophy of Science, vol. 47, p. 511532.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffiths, P. E. 1997 What Emotions Really Are, Chicago, Chicago University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffiths, P. E. et Gray, R. D. 1994 «Developmental Systems and Evolutionary Explanation», The Journal of Philosophy, vol. 91, p. 277304.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hardcastle, V. G. 1992 «Reduction, Explanatory Extension, and the Mind-Brain Sciences», Philosophy of Science, vol. 59, p. 408428.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Isaac, G. 1983 «Aspects of Human Evolution», dans Evolution from Molecules to Men, sous la direction de Bendall, D.Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, p. 509543.Google Scholar
Kaplan, S. 1992 «Environmental Preference in a Knowledge-Seeking, Knowledge- Using Organism», dans Barkow, Cosmides et Tooby, 1992, p. 581598.Google Scholar
Kim, J. 1993 «Multiple Realization and the Metaphysics of Reduction», dans Supervenience and Mind, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, p. 309335.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, J. 1998 «The Mind-Body Problem after Fifty Years», dans Current Issues in Philosophy of Mind, supplément de Philosophy, nº43, sous la direction d'O'Hear, A., Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, p. 321.Google Scholar
Kimura, D. 1992 «Sex Differences in the Brain», Scientific American, nº 267, p. 118125.Google ScholarPubMed
Kinkaid, H. 1990 «Molecular Biology and the Unity of Science», Philosophy of Science, vol. 57, p. 575593.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, Patricia 1993 Freud's Dream, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press.Google Scholar
Kitcher, Philip 1981 «Explanatory Unification», Philosophy of Science, vol. 48, p. 507531; repris dans The Philosophy of Science, sous la direction de R. Boyd, P. Gasper et J. Trout, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 1991, p. 329–347.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, Philip 1993 «Function and Design», Midwest Studies in Philosophy, vol. 18, p. 379397.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kosslyn, S. 1994 «On Cognitive Neuroscience», Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, vol. 6, p. 297303.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lewontin, R. 1990 «The Evolution of Cognition», dans An Invitation to Cognitive Science : Thinking, sous la direction de Osherson, D. N. et Smith, E. E., Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, p. 229246.Google Scholar
Lips, H. 1988 Sex and Gender: An Introduction, Mountain View, Mayfield Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Mayr, E. 1988 Toward a New Philosophy of Biology, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
McCauley, R. 1993 «Cross-Scientific Study and the Complexity of Psychology», dans Annals of Theoretical Psychology, vol. 9, sous la direction de Rappard, H. et al., New York, Plenum Press, p. 165172.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millikan, R. G. 1984 Language, Thought, and other Biological Categories, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millikan, R. G. 1989 «In Defense of Proper Functions», Philosophy of Science, vol. 56, p. 288302.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millikan, R. G. 1999 «Historical Kinds and the “Special Sciences”», Philosophical Studies, vol. 95, p. 4565.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mundale, J. et Bechtel, W. 1996 «Integreting Neuroscience, Psychology, and Evolutionary Biology through a Teleological Conception of Function», Minds and Machines, vol. 6, p. 481505.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, E. 1961 The Structure of Science, New York, Harcourt, Brace and World.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neander, K. 1991 «Functions as Selected Effects : The Conceptual Analyst's Defense», Philosophy of Science, vol. 58, p. 168184.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oppenheim, P. et Putnam, H. 1958 «The Unity of Science as a Working Hypothesis», dans Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 2, sous la direction de Feigl, H.Maxwell, G. et Scriven, M.Minneapolis, The University of Minnesota Press; trad, de P.Jacob sous le titre «L'unité de la science : une hypothèse de travail», dans De Vienne à Cambridge, sous la direction de P. Jacob, Paris, Gallimard, 1980, p. 337–377.Google Scholar
Orians, G. H. et Heerwagen, J. H. 1992 «Evolved Responses to Landscapes», dans Barkow, Cosmides et Tooby, 1992, p. 555579.Google Scholar
Pinker, S. 1997 How the Mind Works, New York, Norton.Google Scholar
Poirier, P. 2000 «L'empire contre-attaque : le retour de la réduction psychophysique», Philosophiques, vol. 27, nº 1, p. 3962.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Poirier, P. et Faucher, L. ms. «L'unification évolutionniste de la psychologies».Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1967 «Psychological Predicates», repris sous le titre «The Nature of Mental States», dans Putnam, H., Mind, Language, and Reality, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1975, p. 429440.Google Scholar
Richardson, R. C. 1996 «The Prospects for an Evolutionary Psychology : Human Language and Human Rationality», Minds and Machines, vol. 6, p. 541557.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rose, L. et Marshall, F. 1996 «Meat Eating, Hominid Sociality, and Home Bases Revisited», Current Anthropology, vol. 37, p. 307338.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shapiro, L. A. 1998 «Do's and Don'ts for Darwinizing Psychology», dans The Evolution of Mind, sous la direction de Dellarosa, D.Cummins, R. et Allen, C.Oxford, Oxford University Press, p. 243259.Google Scholar
Shepard, R. 1987 «Evolution of a Mesh between Principles of the Mind and Regularities of the World», dans The Latest on the Best, sous la direction de Dupre, J., Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, p. 251275.Google Scholar
Shepard, R. 1990 «A Possible Evolutionary Basis for Trichromacy», dans Perceiving, Measuring, and Using Color, sous la direction de Brill, M., Washington, SPIE Proceedings series, vol. 1250, p. 301309.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shepard, R. 1992 «The Perceptual Organization of Colors : An Adaptation to Regularities of the Terrestrial World?», dans Barkow, Cosmides et Tooby, 1992, p. 495532.Google Scholar
Silverman, I. et Eals, M. 1992 «Sex Differences in Spatial Abilities : Evolutionary Theory and Data», dans Barkow, Cosmides et Tooby, 1992, p. 533549.Google Scholar
Silverman, I. et Philips, K. 1993 «Effects of Estrogen Changes during the Menstrual Cycle on Spatial Performance», Ethology and Sociobiology, vol. 14, p. 257270.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sterelny, K. 1996 «Explanatory Pluralism in Evolutionary Biology», Biology and Philosophy, vol. 11, p. 193214.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sterelny, K.«An Evolutionary Approach : Can Darwin's View of Life Shed Light on Human Sexuality?», dans Theories of Human Sexuality, sous la direction de Geer, J. et O'Donohue, W., New York, Plenum Press, p. 91125.Google Scholar
Tinbergen, N. 1963 «On Aims and Methods of Ethology», Zeitschrift für Tierpsychologie, vol. 20, p. 410433.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wimsatt, W. 1976 «Reductionism, Levels of Organization, and the Mind-Body Problem», dans Consciousness and the Brain : A Scientific and Philosophical Inquiry, sous la direction de Globus, G.Maxwell, G. et Savodnik, I.New York, Plenum Press, p. 205267CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wimsatt, W. 1997 «Aggregativity: Reductive Heuristics for Finding Emergence», Philosophy of Science, vol. 64, Proceedings, p. S372S384.CrossRefGoogle Scholar