Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-t5pn6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-16T07:08:13.762Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Mind, Brain and Mental Illness

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 January 2009

Leslie Stevenson
Affiliation:
University of St Andrews

Extract

The distinction between mental illness and bodily illness would seem to presuppose some sort of distinction between mind and body. But dualist theories that the mind is a substance separable from the body, or that mental events could occur without any bodily events, raise ancient conceptual problems, which I do not propose to review here. What I want to do is to examine the psychiatric implications of materialist theories, which hold that the mind is the brain, or a function of the brain. If all character has a basis in chemistry, can we still attribute some mental distress to character and some to chemistry, as if the two categories were different?

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 1977

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Frankl, Victor E., ‘Reductionism and Nihilism’, in Beyond Reductionism, Koestler, and Smythies, (eds.), (London: Hutchinson, 1969), 399.Google Scholar

2 Stevenson, Leslie, ‘Applied Philosophy’, Metaphilosophy I, No. 3 (1970), 258267.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

3 Smart, J. J. C., Philosophy and Scientific Realism (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1963), 107.Google Scholar

4 Armstrong, D. M., A Materialist Theory of the Mind (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1968), 1.Google Scholar

5 See the translations from Brentano, in Realism and the Background of Phenomenology, Chisholm, R. M. (ed.), (Glencoe: The Free Press, 1960)Google Scholar. Although Brentano's criterion will agree with the Cartesian one for most mental phenomena, there may be sensations such as pain which are conscious but without intentionality, and (if Freud was right) there may be desires which are unconscious but are desires for something.

6 ‘The Factors of Insanities’, in Selected Writings of J. Hughlings Jackson, Taylor, J. (ed.), (London: Hodder and Stoughton, 1932)Google Scholar. The passage is quoted by SirSymonds, Charles in ‘Disease of Mind and Disorder of Brain’, British Medical Journal 5191 (2 07 1960), 15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

7 Smart, J. J. C., ‘Sensations and Brain-Processes’, Philosophical Review 68 (1959), 142.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

8 Op. cit. note 4, 41.

9 Op. cit. note 4, 57.

10 Macklin, Ruth, ‘Mental Health and Mental Illness: Some Problems of Definition and Concept Formation’, Philosophy of Science 39, No. 3 (1972), 346.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

11 Op. cit. note 10, 357–358.

12 Macalpine, Ida and Hunter, Richard, ‘The Pathography of the Past’, Times Literary Supplement 3758 (15 03 1974), 256257.Google Scholar

13 Drury, M. O'C., The Danger of Words (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1973), Chapter 2, ‘Science and Psychology’.Google Scholar

14 Peters, R. S., The Concept of Motivation (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1958), 12.Google Scholar

15 Szasz, T. S., The Myth of Mental Illness, new and abbreviated edition (London: Paladin, 1972), 155156.Google Scholar

16 Szasz thus presupposes that explanation by reasons is not a form of causal explanation; cf. Peters in op. cit. note 14.

17 Strawson, P. F., Individuals (London: Methuen, 1959), Chapter 3, ‘Persons’.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

18 Szasz, , op. cit. note 15, 102103.Google Scholar

19 Szasz, T. S., Ideology and Insanity (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1974), 13.Google Scholar

20 Miller, Henry, ‘The Abuse of Psychiatry’, Encounter 34, No. 5 (05 1970), 26.Google Scholar

21 Stafford-Clark, D., Psychiatry for Students Vol. I (London: Allen & Unwin, 4th edn, 1974), 180Google Scholar. See also Gattozzi, A. A., Lithium in the Treatment of Mood Disorders (Rockville, Maryland: National Institute of Mental Health, 1970, revised 1974).Google Scholar

22 Glen, A. I. M. and Reading, H. W., ‘Regulatory Action of Lithium in Manie-Depressive Illness’, The Lancet 7840 (1 12 1973), 12391241.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

23 Davidson, Donald, ‘On Mental Events’, in Experience and Theory Foster, L. and Swanson, (eds.) (London: Duckworth, 1970)Google Scholar; ‘The Material Mind’, in Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science, IV, Suppes, et al. (ed.) (Amsterdam: North-Holland, 1973)Google Scholar; ‘Psychology as Philosophy’ in Philosophy of Psychology, Brown, S. C. (ed.) (London: Macmillan, 1974).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

24 Nagel, T., ‘Physicalism’, Philosophical Review 74 (1965)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Taylor, C., ‘Mind-body Identity, a Side Issue?’, Philosophical Review 76 (1967)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Fodor, J., Psychological Explanation (New York: Random House, 1968), Chapter 3.Google Scholar

25 Davidson, D., ‘Causal Relations’, Journal of Philosophy 64 (1967), 691703CrossRefGoogle Scholar. On the basis of this insight, Davidson can argue that explanation by reasons if a form of causal explanation after all (contra Peters)—see his ‘Actions, Reasons and Causes’, Journal of Philosophy 60 (1963), 685700.Google Scholar

26 Glover, J., Responsibility (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1970), 119.Google Scholar

27 Flew, A., Crime or Disease? (London: Macmillan, 1973), 7071.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

28 For more discussion of the concept of illness, see Margolis, J., Negativities: The Limits of Life (Columbus, Ohio: Charles E. Merrill, 1975), Chapter 7.Google Scholar

29 Stafford-Clark, , op. cit. note 21, 102103.Google Scholar

30 Laing, R. D. and Esterson, A., Sanity, Madness and the Family (London: Tavistock, 1964)Google Scholar, preface to second edition (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1970), 12.

31 As Drury points out in talking of ‘the fallacy of the alchemists’ in Chapter 1 of op. cit. note 13.

32 Op. cit. note 13, Chapter 5, ‘Madness and Religion’.

33 Previous versions of this paper have been read at the Philosophy Club in the University of St Andrews, at the State University of New York at Albany, and at the Western Psychiatric Institute and Clinic in the University of Pittsburgh. I am grateful to the discussions on those occasions, and to Adam Morton, Tom Nagel, Peter Railton, Richard Rorty, and Alan Spiro at Princeton, for criticisms which have saved me from many errors. I am also indebted to the University of St Andrews for a period of sabbatical leave, and to the Philosophy Department of Princeton University for encouraging me to come as a Visiting Fellow.