Hostname: page-component-7c8c6479df-24hb2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-03-29T14:49:10.078Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Words and Intentions

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 January 2009

Edmond L. Wright
Affiliation:
Pembroke College, Oxford

Extract

The relationship of word-meaning to speaker's-meaning has not been examined thoroughly enough. Some philosophical problems are solved and others made plainer if the full consequences of a proper relationship between these two is worked out.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 1977

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Grice, H. P., ‘Meaning’, Philosophical Review 46 (1957), 377388CrossRefGoogle Scholar; ‘Utterer's Meaning and Intentions‘, Philosophical Review 78 (1969), 147177.Google Scholar

2 Wittgenstein, Ludwig, Philosophical Investigations, Anscombe, G. E. M. (ed.) (Oxford: Blackwell, 1967)Google Scholar; The Blue and Brown Books, pref. by Rhees, R. (Oxford: Blackwell, 1960)Google Scholar; Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics, von Wright, G. H., Rhees, R., and Anscombe, G. E. M. (eds.), translated by Anscombe, G. E. M. (Oxford: Blackwell, 1956).Google Scholar

3 Palmer, Leonard, Descriptive and Comparative Linguistics (London, 1972), 321.Google Scholar

4 Augustine, St, De Magistro, translated by Russell, Robert P. in The Teacher; The Free Choice of the Will; Grace and Free Will (Washington, 1968), 1415.Google Scholar

5 Wittgenstein, , PI, section 143 et seq.Google Scholar

6 Ibid., section 217.

7 Van de Vate, Dwight, ‘The Appeal to Force’, Philosophy and Rhetoric 8 (1975), 4360.Google Scholar

8 Wittgenstein, , PI, section 199.Google Scholar

9 It is ironic to see in these very same sections the Master himself being corrected by his editor. In section 226 of PI, p. 86e, the manuscript read, ‘Suppose someone gets the series of numbers, 1, 3, 5, 7, … by working out the series x 2+1’. The editor has corrected this to ‘Suppose someone gets the series of numbers 1, 3, 5, 7, … by working out the series 2x+1’. How do we know that this is what Wittgenstein meant? Perhaps he meant ‘Suppose someone gets the series of numbers 1, 2, 5, 10, … by working out the series x 2+1’—which takes the variable x to move through the values 0, 1, 2, 3, 4, … Or perhaps he meant ‘… the series 2, 5, 26, 676, … by working out the series x 2+1’—taking the value of the variable x to be first 1, and thereafter the number produced by the formula. Or perhaps …

10 St Augustine, , De Magistro, p. 41.Google Scholar

11 Copley, J., Shift of Meaning (London, 1961), 8586.Google Scholar

12 Schiffer, Stephen R., Meaning (Oxford University Press, 1972).Google Scholar

13 SirGardiner, Alan H., The Theory of Speech and Language (Oxford University Press, 1932), 52Google Scholar. There are distinct anticipations of Grice in Gardiner, (pp. 20, 79, 87, 100101)Google Scholar and in the author to whom he frequently refers, Wegener, Ph., Untersuchungen über die Grundfragen des Sprachlebens (Halle, 1885), 6769.Google Scholar

14 Austin, J. L., ‘A Plea for Excuses’ in Philosophical Papers (Oxford University Press, 1970), 201.Google Scholar

15 Anscombe, G. E. M., Intention (Oxford: Blackwell, 1957).Google Scholar

16 Feinberg, Joel, ‘Action and Responsibility’ in Philosophy in America, by Black, Max (ed.) (London: Allen and Unwin, 1964), 134160 (p. 146).Google Scholar

17 Wittgenstein, , PI, section 659.Google Scholar

18 If the argument of this article is cogent, one can only arrive at a speaker's-meaning version of ‘knowing-that’, never at a fixed word-meaning version.

19 Merton, R. K., Social Theory and Social Structure (New York: Free Press, 1968), 81ff.Google Scholar

20 Douglas, Mary (ed.), Rules and Meanings (Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1973)Google Scholar. One might explore the relationship between tacit assumptions and the enthymeme as it appears in Aristotle's analysis of rhetoric.

21 Merton, , p. 81.Google Scholar

22 Johnstone, Henry W. Jr, Philosophy and Argument (University of Pennsylvania, 1959), 129.Google Scholar

23 Canfield, John V., ‘Criteria and the Rules of Language’, Philosophical Review 83 (1974), 7081.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

24 Nell, Edward J., ‘The Hardness of the Logical “Must”’, Analysis 21 (19601961), 6872 (p. 70).Google Scholar

25 Schutz, Alfred, Collected Papers. Vol. I: The Problem of Social Reality (The Hague: Nijhoff, 1962), 3132.Google Scholar

26 Schutz, , p. 32.Google Scholar

27 Schutz, , p. 33.Google Scholar

28 Schiffer, op. cit.

29 Lewis, David K., Convention (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1969).Google Scholar

30 Schutz, Alfred, On Phenomenology and Social Relations: Selected Writings, Wagner, Helmut R. (ed.) (Chicago, 1973), 199.Google Scholar

31 Nell, , p. 70.Google Scholar

32 Pitcher, George, ‘About the Same’ in Ludwig Wittgenstein: Philosophy and Language, Ambrose, Alice and Lazerowitz, Morris (ed.) (London: Allen and Unwin, 1972), 120139.Google Scholar

33 See Jones, J. R., ‘Characters and Resemblances’, Philosophical Review 60 (1951), 551562 (p. 561)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Goodman, Nelson ‘Seven Strictures on Similarity’ in Experience and Theory, Foster, L. and Swanson, J. W. (eds.) (London, 1970), 2526Google Scholar. It has often been said that any two things can be shown to be alike. What has not been pointed out is that such likenings would represent fictitious, ad hoc intention.

34 Wittgenstein, , PI, sections 224 and 225, p. 86e.Google Scholar

35 Nell, , p. 70.Google Scholar

37 de Saussure, Ferdinand, Course in General Linguistics, Bally, Charles and Sechehaye, Albert (ed.) in collaboration with Albert Reidlinger, translated by Baskin, Wade (London, 1960)Google Scholar; first edition Paris, 1916.

38 Wittgenstein, , RFM, sections 113 to 116.Google Scholar

39 Stroud, Barry, ‘Wittgenstein and Logical Necessity’, Philosophical Review 74 (1965), 504518.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

40 Bogen, James, Wittgenstein's Philosophy of Language (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1972), 193ff.Google Scholar

41 Chibara, Charles S., ‘Wittgenstein and Logical Compulsion’, Analysis 21 (19601961), 136140.Google Scholar

42 Mundle, C. W. K., A Critique of Linguistic Philosophy (Oxford University Press, 1970), 197.Google Scholar

43 Doorbar, Roger, ‘Meaning, Rules and Behaviour’, Mind 80 (1971), 2940.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

44 See Wright, E. L., ‘Similarity and Contiguity in Relation to Meaning’ (unpublished D.Phil, thesis, University of Oxford, 1975), ch. VIII.Google Scholar

45 Kripke, Saul A., ‘Naming and Necessity’ in Semantics of Natural Language, Davidson, Donald and Karman, Gilbert (eds.) (Dordrecht, 1972), 253355.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

46 Kuipers, Aert H., ‘On Symbols, Distinctions and Markedness’, Lingua 36 (1975), 3146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar