Hostname: page-component-7c8c6479df-ph5wq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-03-27T14:44:12.627Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Darwin, Teleology and Taxonomy

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 February 2009

Andrew Woodfield
Affiliation:
St John's College, Oxford

Extract

Darwinism is ‘much more than a theory’, said the German botanist Albert Wigand in 1875; ‘it is a frame of mind which dominates thought, a resuscitated “Naturphilosophie”, in which the terms “Polarity”, “Totality”, “Subject”, “Object” are replaced by terms such as “Struggle for Existence”, “Inheritance”, “Selection”, and so on.’ Subsequent events have indicated that Wigand had a point. But it is not clear to us yet what exactly the point is. Interest in Man's Place in Nature, and in his alleged biological uniqueness as a language-user and tool-maker, is as great now as it was in 1871 when Darwin's Descent of Man was first published. We now have access to well over a hundred years' worth of material sparked off by The Origin of Species, linking Darwin's theory of evolution by natural selection to almost every field under the sun. Yet the precise status of his theory is still the subject of vigorous controversy in philosophy of science.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 1973

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 In his 3-volume critique Der Darwinismus und die Naturforschung Newtons und Cuviers. Quoted by Ràdl, Emanuel in The History of Biological Theories, p. 62. Oxford U.P. 1930.Google Scholar

2 Monod, Jacques. Le Hasard et la Nécessité. Éditions du Seuil, Paris. 1970Google Scholar. English edition translated by Wainhouse, Austryn, London; Collins 1972.Google Scholar

3 For a contemporary example, see Powell, Enoch's article in The Spectator, 7445, 6 03 1971, p. 312.Google Scholar

4 The Origin of Species, 1st edition, p. 434Google Scholar. (All page-numbers refer to the Penguin version of the first edition of O.S., edited by J. W. Burrow.)

5 Ibid. pp. 169–170.

6 Ibid. p. 170.

7 From Forerunners of Darwin, p. 40Google Scholar. Edited by Glass, Bentley et al. The Johns Hopkins Press, 1959.Google Scholar

8 For an interesting paper on this topic, see Young, R. M., ‘Darwin's Metaphor: Does Nature Select?’, The Monist, 07 1971.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

9 Letter from Darwin to Lyell, , 04 1860Google Scholar. Life and Letters of Charles Darwin, (ed. Darwin, Francis). Vol. II.Google Scholar

10 Critique of Teleological Judgment. Actually, Kant appears to make two distinctions which are not kept entirely separate, one between relative and absolute purposiveness, the other between external and internal. For a discussion of Kant's views, see McFarland, J. D., Kant's Concept of Teleology, especially Chapter 6. Edinburgh U.P., 1970.Google Scholar

11 Hume, David, Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, part VIII, p. 185. Kemp-Smith edition, 1947.Google Scholar

12 Origin of Species, p. 348.Google Scholar

13 See, for example, Flew, A.'s article ‘The Structure of Darwinism’ in Penguin New Biology, 28 (1959)Google Scholar; Scriven, Michael's paper ‘Explanation and Prediction in Evolutionary Theory’, in Science, 130, 477 (1959)CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Barker, A. D., ‘An Approach to the Theory of Natural Selection’Google Scholar and Lee, K. K., ‘Popper's Falsifiability and Darwin's Natural Selection’ in Philosophy, 44 (1969)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Finally, Ruse, Michael's detailed analysis, ‘Natural Selection in The Origin of SpeciesStudies in History and Philosophy of Science, 02 1971.Google Scholar

14 Kerkut, G. A., Implications of Evolution, Pure and Applied Biology Monographs 1960.Google Scholar

15 I borrow this formulation from a paper by Ayala, F. J., ‘Teleological Explanations in Evolutionary Biology’, in Philosophy of Science, 37, No. 1. 03 1970.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

16 In my necessarily brief treatment of the species concept, a number of problematic issues have had to be skipped. For a fuller picture, see Hull, D. L. (1965)Google Scholar and Ruse, M. (1969) in Brit. J. Phil. ScienceGoogle Scholar; and Lehman, Hugh, Philosophy of Science, 1967Google Scholar; plus discussions (1970, both journals).

17 Quine, W. V. O., Word and Object, M.I.T. 1960Google Scholar. Motto before the Preface: ‘“Ontology recapitulates philosophy”—James Grier Miller.’ Häckel's original Law of Biogenesis was, of course, ‘Ontogeny recapitulates phylogeny’. The fortunes of this idea and its parody trace a circle from Darwin to Häckel to Miller to Quine, and now back to Darwin again. For the wider philosophical issues involved in the question of the reality of species, see Harré, R., The Principles of Scientific Thinking, Macmillan 1970, pp. 196200CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Also Quine's essay, ‘Natural Kinds’ in the collection Ontological Relativity and Other Essays.

18 For a detailed argument showing that organs are functionally defined, see Beckner, M.'s The Biological Way of Thought, Univ. Calif., 1968, pp. 112118.Google Scholar

19 Darwin, (1871), especially Chapter V.Google Scholar

20 Dobzhansky, Th., Mankind Evolving, Yale U.P. 1962, especially Chapter 12.Google Scholar