Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-c4f8m Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-24T03:43:42.236Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Vague Music

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 March 2011

Roy Sorensen*
Affiliation:
Washington University in St. Louis

Abstract

Is listening to (purely instrumental) music like looking through a kaleidoscope? Formalists contend that music is meaningless. Most music theorists concede that this austere thesis is surprisingly close to the truth. Nevertheless, they refute formalism with a little band of diffusely referential phenomena, such as musical quotation, onomatopoeia, exemplification, and leitmotifs. These curiosities ought to be pressed into a new campaign against assumptions that vagueness can only arise in the semantically lush setting of language. Just as the discovery of extremophilic bacteria led biologists to revise their opinions about the scope and preconditions of life, the marginal forms of reference that survive in the semantic desert of absolute music should lead philosophers to revise their assumptions much about scope and preconditions of vagueness.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Russell, Bertrand, ‘Vagueness’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy and Psychology 1, (1923), 8492. Russell extends vagueness beyond language to maps and photographs. He does not distinguish between vagueness as the possession of borderline cases (as in ‘thirty-ish’) and vagueness as underspecificity (as in ‘thirty-something’ which encompasses a wide but precise interval)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

2 Lerdahl, Fred and Ray, Jackendoff, A Generative Theory of Tonal Music (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1996). A wrong note is like a grammatical error. Just as a native speaker can identify a solecism in a sentence he never heard before, members of a concert audience can identify a wrong note in a novel compositionGoogle Scholar.

3 Davies, Stephen, Musical Meaning and Expression (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1994)Google Scholar chapter 1.

4 Levinson, Jerrold, ‘The Concept of Music’, in his Music, Art, and Metaphysics (Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press, 1990), 267–78Google Scholar, 272.

5 Hamilton, AndyAesthetics and Music (New York, NY: Continuum Press, 2007), 4055Google Scholar.

6 Cloarec-Heiss, Frances, ‘From natural language to drum language: An economical encoding procedure in Banda-Linda, Central African Republic’ Language diversity and cognitive representations edited by Fuchs, Catherine, Robert, Stéphane, (Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishers, 1999)Google Scholar.

7 Smith, Adam, Philosophical Subjects (London, 1795)Google Scholar, 133.

8 Kivy, Peter, Sound and Semblance (Princeton University Press, 1984), 101Google Scholar.

9 Zahavi, Amotz, ‘Mate selection – a selection for a handicapJournal of Theoretical Biology 53 (1975), 205214CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

10 Pasnau, Robert, ‘What is Sound? Philosophical Quarterly 50 (1999), 309–24CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

11 Scruton, Roger, The Aesthetics of Music (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1997) 221Google Scholar.

12 Walton, Kendall, Mimesis as Make-Believe (Cambridge, Mass., MIT Press, 1990), 340Google Scholar.

13 Perris, Arnold, Music as Propaganda: Art to persuade, art to control (Westport, Connecticut: Greenwood Press, 1985)Google Scholar.

14 Sousa, John Philip, Marching Along (Waterville, Ohio: Integrity Press, 1994), 358Google Scholar.

15 Sorensen, Roy, ‘Vagueness within the Language of Thought’, Philosophical Quarterly 41 (1991), 389413CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

16 Fine, Kit, ‘Vagueness, truth and logic’, Syntheses 54 (1975): 235259Google Scholar, 282. Reprinted in Vagueness: A Reader, Keefe, Rosanna and Smith, Peter (eds.), (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1996), 119150Google Scholar.

17 Wright, Crispin, ‘Language Mastery and the Sorites Paradox’ in Evans and McDowell (eds.) Truth and Meaning (Oxford: Clarendon Press 1976), 223247Google Scholar.

18 Soames, Scott, Understanding Truth (New York: Oxford, 1999), 206212CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

19 Brown, Steven, ‘The “Musilanguage” Model of Music Evolution’ in Wallin, N. L., Merker, B., and Brown, S. (eds.) The Origins of Music. (Cambridge: The MIT Press, 1999), 271301Google Scholar.

20 Williamson, Timothy, ‘Truth and Borderline Cases’ in Korta and Larrazabal (eds.) Truth, rationality, cognition, and music (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 2004), 4566CrossRefGoogle Scholar; 54.

21 Freud, Sigmund, ‘The Unconscious’ in The Pelican Freud Library (Hammondsworth: Penguin Books, 1984) vol. 11, 190191Google Scholar.

22 London, Justin, ‘Musical and Linguistic Speech Acts’, The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 54 (1996), 4964CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

23 Schwartz, Stephen P., ‘Soritic thinking, vagueness, and weakness of will’, New Ideas in Psychology 27 (2009), 1831CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

24 Quinn, Warren, ‘The puzzle of the self-torturer’, Philosophical Studies 59 (1990), 7990CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

25 Shepherd, Roger N, ‘Circularity in Judgments of Relative Pitch’, Journal of the Acoustical Society of America 36 (1964), 23462353CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

26 Huron, David, Sweet Anticipation: Music and the Psychology of Expectation (Cambridge: MIT Press, 2006)Google Scholar.

27 van Fraassen, Bas, ‘On a Kantian Conception of Language’, in Martin, R. M. (ed.) The Paradox of the Liar (New Haven: Yale University Press 1970), 5966Google Scholar.