Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-r6qrq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-26T15:17:20.275Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

An Analysis of Some of J. J. C. Smart's Objections to the ‘Proofs’

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 October 2008

Frank B. Dilley
Affiliation:
Professor of Philosophy, University of Delaware

Extract

I submit as a good rule of thumb (but one which is sometimes wrong) that if a discussion of any major philosophical position or proposition ends with the conclusion that that position or proposition is ‘absurd’ or ‘meaningless’ then a mistake has been made in the discussion. The mistake often turns out to be the accuser's failure to appreciate precisely what the position being attacked really is.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1969

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

page 245 note 1 Smart, J. J. C., ‘The Existence of God’, reprinted in New Essays in Philosophical Theology (SCM Press, 1955), ed. Flew, and Maclntyre, , pp. 2846.Google Scholar Citations of this essay are from this source. This essay is contained also in a number of anthologies and basic text books in introductory philosophy.

page 246 note 1 The quotations are from Lafleur's translation of The Meditations (Bobbs-Merrill, 1960).Google Scholar It makes use of both Latin originals and French translations approved by Descartes. The texts cited aboveare sometimes from Lafleur's conflation of French and Latin editions, however my case can be argued from the Latin text alone. Both Charles Hartshorne and Norman Malcolm, in that chronological order, have argued that existence is a predicate in the Anselmian version of the argument. Malcolm says that ‘although it is an error to regard existence as a property of things that have contingent existence, it does not follow that it is an error to regard necessary existence as a property of God’. The Malcolm paper is reprinted in Plantinga, ed. The Ontologial Argument, the statement in question is on p. 148.

page 247 note 1 St Thomas Aquinas, Summa Contra Gentiles, I, 11, 3. The logical trap is understandable. Necessary existence is a way of being, whereas whether a being exists or not is a matter of fact. It is logically possible that no beings with necessary existence actually exist, argument of Hartshorne from modal logic to the effect that the class of necessary beings cannot be a null class notwithstanding, in my opinion.

page 248 note 1 Geach's observation is that the cosmological arguments are of the form ‘since the world is of such-and-such a nature, there must be some being who made it and keeps it going’, p. 58 of Com mentary on Aquinas' reprinted in The Cosmological Arguments, ed. Burrill, (Doubleday, 1967).Google Scholar He observes further, with regard to the third way, ‘the necessity or contingency that is here in question is not the logical necessity or contingency of some (existential) statement’ (p. 65). Copleston has observed that the argument is not one of logical entailment or analysis but one of a metaphysical analysis involving ontological or causal entailment. See Aquinas (Penguin, n.d.), p. 114.Google Scholar

page 249 note 1 Perhaps the organism analogy is better, perhaps it is not. However it is instructive to note that those who do find the organismic analogy better tend to find the teleological argument one of their chief sources of support. The process tradition, as presented in the works of Whitehead and Hartshorne, are excellent cases in point.

page 249 note 2 Matson, Wallace, The Existence of God (Cornell, 1965), p. 88.Google Scholar

page 250 note 1 See Paley's views on pp. 20, 86 and elsewhere in Natural Theology: Selections, ed. Ferré, (Bobbos-Merrill, 1963).Google Scholar