Hostname: page-component-7c8c6479df-r7xzm Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-03-28T22:21:06.376Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Divine Commands and Arbitrariness

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 October 2008

Paul Rooney
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, University of Liverpool, P.O. Box 147, Liverpool L69 3BX

Abstract

According to the divine command theory of morality, what is right or wrong, good or bad, is entirely dependent on the will and command of God: what He commands is right and what He forbids is wrong just because He commands or forbids it. It is argued here that the principal religious objection to this theory – that if it were true, moral precepts would be arbitrary – is rendered ineffective when due consideration is given to the consequences of God's omnipotence, and in particular, to His rationality and to His responsibility for deciding, in creation, what the characteristics of human nature are to be.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1995

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Brody, B. A., ‘Morality and Religion Reconsidered’. In Helm, P., Divine Commands and Morality (Oxford, 1981)Google Scholar.

2 Meynell, H., ‘The Euthyphro Dilemma’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (supplementary volume, 1972Google Scholar). The argument he discusses is in Nowell-Smith, P. H., ‘Morality: Religious and Secular’, to be found in Ramsey, I. T. (ed.), Christian Ethics and Contemporary Philosophy (London, 1966).Google Scholar

3 One can impose rules on oneself, but in such a circumstance one can hardly be said to be constrained by them.

4 Traditionally, God cannot change His mind, as it were, since He is held to be immutable. ‘Eternity principally characterizes God who is utterly unchangeable’ – Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, Ia, 10. But that doctrine is consistent with divine commands changing from time to time, since God can eternally will change while not changing His will.

5 Gunton, C. E., The One, The Three and the Many (Cambridge, 1993), p. 122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

6 Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, Ia, 19.6. The reference is taken from Psalm 115: 3.

7 ‘A standard objection to this theory – let's call it the arbitrariness objection – has long been that it cannot escape the following dilemma. On the one hand, if God has no reason for what He commands, then His commands – and hence morality as well, according to the theory – are fundamentally arbitrary. On the other hand, if God does have reasons for what He commands, then it is those reasons rather than divine commands on which morality ultimately depends. The first horn of the dilemma is said to be too implausible to be acceptable; the second, to abandon the divine-command theory itself.’ Sullivan, S. J., ‘Arbitrariness, divine commands, and morality’, International Journal for the Philosophy of Religion, XXXIII (1993), 3345CrossRefGoogle Scholar; emphasis mine.

8 Scotus, Duns, ‘Quaestiones in Libros Sententiarum’. In Works (Paris, 1891 5).Google Scholar

9 Mann, W. E., ‘The Best of All Possible Worlds’. In MacDonald, S. (ed.), Being and Goodness (Cornell U.P., 1991).Google Scholar

10 Adams, R. M., The Virtue of Faith (O.U.P., 1987), pp. 98–9.Google Scholar

11 Ewing, A. C., ‘The Autonomy of Ethics’. In Ramsey, I. T. (ed.), Prospect for Metaphysics (London, 1961).Google Scholar

12 Anselm, , Proslogion, xi.Google Scholar

13 Anselm, , Cur Deus Homo, i.12.Google Scholar

14 Suarez, F., De Legibus (London, 1944), p. 286.Google Scholar

15 Abelard, P., Ethics, ed. Luscombe, D. E. (Oxford, 1971), p. 29.Google Scholar

16 Price, R., A Review of the Principal Questions in Morals, ed. Raphael, D. D. (Oxford, 1974), p. 49.Google Scholar

17 See footnote in Raphael's edition, op. cit. p. 49.

18 Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, Ia–IIae, 94.5.

20 Op. cit. 93.4.

21 Acts 7: 52.

22 Romans 9: 20–1.

23 P. Abelard, Super Epist. ad Rom. 2.6.

24 Swinburne, R., The Coherence of Theism (Oxford, 1986), pp. 186–7.Google Scholar

25 There is an interesting example of what the imagination can produce in the way of rightful torture in Orson Scott Card's novel Xenocide (London, 1991).Google Scholar

26 Aquinas, op. cit. Ia–IIae, 186.

27 Mahoney, J., The Making of Moral Theology (Oxford, 1987), p. 179.Google Scholar

28 Paul, Pope John II, Veritatis Splendor (The Vatican, 1993), p. 98.Google Scholar

29 Romans 3:8.

30 Aquinas, op. cit. Ia–IIae, 341.

31 Mahoney, op. cit. p. 246.

32 Gunton, op. cit. p. 57.

33 Brown, P., ‘Religious Morality: A Reply to Flew and Campbell’, Mind LXXVII (1968), 577–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

34 Douglas, M., Purity and Danger (London, 1979), p. 43.Google Scholar