Hostname: page-component-7c8c6479df-8mjnm Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-03-28T01:21:48.871Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Methodological solipsism considered as a research strategy in cognitive psychology1

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 February 2010

J. A. Fodor
Affiliation:
Department of Psychology. Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Cambridge, Mass 02139

Abstract

The paper explores the distinction between two doctrines, both of which inform theory construction in much of modern cognitive psychology: the representational theory of mind and the computational theory of mind. According to the former, propositional attitudes are to be construed as relations that organisms bear to mental representations. According to the latter, mental processes have access only to formal (nonsemantic) properties of the mental representations over which they are defined.

The following claims are defended: (1) That the traditional dispute between “rational” and “naturalistic” psychology is plausibly viewed as an argument about the status of the computational theory of mind. Rational psychologists accept a formality condition on the specification of mental processes; naturalists do not. (2) That to accept the formality condition is to endorse a version of methodological solipsism. (3) That the acceptance of some such condition is warranted, at least for that part of psychology which concerns itself with theories of the mental causation of behavior. This is because: (4) such theories require nontransparent taxonomies of mental states; and (5) nontransparent taxonomies individuate mental states without reference to their semantic properties. Equivalently, (6) nontransparent taxonomies respect the way that the organism represents the object of its propositional attitudes to itself, and it is this representation which functions in the causation of behavior.

The final section of the paper considers the prospect for a naturalistic psychology: one which defines its generalizations over relations between mental representations and their environmental causes, thus seeking to account for the semantic properties of propositional attitudes. Two related arguments are proposed, both leading to the conclusion that no such research strategy is likely to prove fruitful.

Type
Target Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1980

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Balderrama, N., & Maldanado, H. (1973) Ontogeny of behavior in the praying mantis. Journal of Insect Physiology 19: 319336. [RS]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bennett, J. (1976) Linguistic behaviour. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press. [GH]Google Scholar
Bentley, A. F. (1954) Inquiry into inquiries. In: Ratner, S. (ed), Essays in social theory. Boston: Beacon Press. [RS]Google Scholar
Berlinski, D. (1976) On systems analysis. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. [RS]Google Scholar
Bloomfield, I. (1933) Language. London: Allen and Unwin. [JAF]Google Scholar
Carnap, R. (1947) Meaning and necessity. Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press. [LTC]Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. (1959) Review of Skinner's Verbal Behavior. Language, 35: 2658. [JAF]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, L. J., Fodor, J. A., and Katz, J. J. (eds.) (1966) Critical study of The structural of language. Philosophical Quarterly 16: 165177. [LJC]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, L. J., Fodor, J. A., and Katz, J. J. (1970) What is the ability to refer to things, as a constituent of a language- speaker's competence? In: Visentini, B. (ed), Linguaggi nella societá e nella tecnica, pp. 255268. Milan: Edizioni di Communita. [LJC]Google Scholar
Cummins, R. (1975) “The philosophical problem of truth-of. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 5: 103122. [RC]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cummins, R. (1977) Programs in the explanation of behavior. Philosophy of Science 44: 269287. [RC]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cummins, R. (forthcoming) Explaining cognitive capacities. [RC]Google Scholar
Davidson, D. (1963) Actions, reasons, and causes. Journal of Philosophy 60: 685700. [LHD]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, D. (1967) Causal relations. Journal of Philosophy 64: 691703. [LHD]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, D. (1969) True to the facts. Journal of Philosophy 66: 748764. [JJCS]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, D. (1974) Psychology as philosophy. In: Brown, S. C. (ed), Philosophy of psychology. London: Macmillan. [JJCS]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, D. (1975) Thought and talk. In: Guttenplan, S. (ed), Mind and language. Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press. [SPS]Google Scholar
Davis, L. H. (1974) Disembodied brains. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 52: 121–32. [LHD]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dennett, D. C. (1969) Content and consciousness. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. [CH, SPS]Google Scholar
Descartes, R. (1931) Meditations on first philosophy, trans. Haldane, E. S. and Ross, C. R. T.. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press. [JAF]Google Scholar
Dewey, J., & Bentley, A. F. (1949) Knowing and the known. Boston: Beacon Press. [RS]Google Scholar
Donnellan, K. S. (1962) Necessity and criteria. Journal of Philosophy 59: 647658. [JJK]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dreyfus, H. L. (1979) What computers can't do. Rev. ed. New York: Harper & Row. [HLD]Google Scholar
Dreyfus, H. L. (1980) Husserl on intentionality. Montgomery, Vt.: Bradford Books. [HLD]Google Scholar
Dreyfus, H. L. and Dreyfus, C. (1979) The scope, limits and training of three models of aircraft pilot emergency response behavior. Operations Research Center, Univ. of California, Berkeley. [HLD]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Field, H. (1972) Tarski's theory of truth. Journal of Philosophy 69: 347375. [JAF]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. A. (1975) The language of thought. New York: Thomas Y. Crowell. [LTC. RC, JAF. PWJ, JJK, CR]Google Scholar
Fodor, J. A. (1978) Tom Swift and his procedural grandmother. Cognition 6: 229247. [JAF]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. A. (1979) Propositional attitudes. The Monist (special issue on philosophy and cognitive psychology), forthcoming. [JAF]Google Scholar
Fodor, J. D., Fodor, J. A., & Carrett, M. F. (1975) The psychological unreality of semantic representations. Linguistic Inquiry 6: 515531. [PWJ]Google Scholar
Frege, C. (1952) On sense and reference. In: Geach, P., and Black, M. (eds.), Translations from the philosophical writings of Cottlob Frege, pp. 5678. Oxford: Blackwell. [JJK]Google Scholar
Geach, P. (1957) Mental acts. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.& [JAF]Google Scholar
Gibson, J. J. (1966) The senses considered as perceptual systems. Boston, Mass.: Houghton. [GH, AW]Google Scholar
Goodman, N. (1955) Fact, fiction, and forecast, pp. 8792, 106119. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill. [JJK]Google Scholar
Goodman, N. (1978) Ways of world making. Indianapolis: Hackett. [JAF]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grice, H. P. (1961) The causal theory of perception. Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 35: 121168. [LHD]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grice, H. P. (1975) Logic and conversation. In Cole, P., & Morgan, J. (eds.). Syntax and semantics, vol. 3, p. 53. New York; Academic Press. [JJK]Google Scholar
Harman, C. (1973) Thought. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton Univ. Press. [GH]Google Scholar
Harman, C. (1980) Reasoning and explanatory coherence. American Philosophical Quarterly 16: 2. [GH]Google Scholar
Hintikka, J. (1975) The intentions of intentionality and other new models for modalities. Dordrecht: Reidel. [ RS]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Husserl, E. (1962) Ideas. New York: Collier Books. [HLD]Google Scholar
Husserl, E. (1970a) Logical investigations. New York: Humanities Press. [HLD]Google Scholar
Husserl, E. (1970b) The crisis of European sciences and transcendental phenomenology. Evanston. Ill.: Northwestern University Press. [HLD]Google Scholar
James, W. (1890) Principles of psychology, vol. I. (repr., New York: Dover, 1950) New York: Henry Holt. [JAF]Google Scholar
Katz, F. M., & Katz, J. J. (1977) Is necessity the mother of intension? The Philosophical Review 8: 7096. [JJK]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Katz, J. J. (1972) Semantic theory. New York: Harper & Row. [PWJ, JJK]Google Scholar
Katz, J. J. (1977a) A proper theory of names. Philosophical Studies 31: 180. [JJK]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Katz, J. J. (1977b) Propositional structure and illocutionary force. New York: Crowell, Harper & Bow. [JJK]Google Scholar
Katz, J. J. (1977c) The real status of semantic representations. Linguistic Inquiry 8: 559584. [PWJ]Google Scholar
Katz, J. J. (1979) The neo-classical theory of references. In: French, P., Uehling, T. E., & Wettstein, H. (eds.), Midwest studies in philosophy: Contemporary perspectives in the philosophy of language, pp. 103124. Minneapolis: Univ. of Minnesota Press. [JJK]Google Scholar
Katz, J. J., & Fodor, J. A. (1964) The structure of a semantic theory. In: Fodor, J. A., & Katz, J. J. (eds), The structure of language, pp. 479518. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall. [LJC]Google Scholar
Kripke, S. (1971) Identity and necessity. In: Munit, M. (ed.), Identity and individuation. New York: New York Univ. Press. [RS]Google Scholar
Katz, J. J. (1972) Naming and necessity. In: Davidson, D., & Harman, C. (eds.), Sensantics of Natural Language, pp. 253356. Dordrecht: Reidel. [JJK]Google Scholar
Minsky, M. (1975) A framework for representing knowledge. In: Winston, P. H. (ed), The psychology of computer vision. New York: McGrawHill. [HLD]Google Scholar
Osherson, D. N. (19741976) Logical abilities in children: 1. Organization of length and class concepts - Empirical consequences of a Piagetian formalism; 2. Logical inference - Underlying operations; 3. Reasoning in adolescence - Deductive inference; 4. Reasoning and concepts. Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum. [PWJ]Google Scholar
Pattee, H. H. (1977) Dynamic and linguistic modes of complex systems. International Journal of General Systems 8: 259266. [RS]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Patten, B. C., Bosserman, R. W., Finn, J. T., & Cale, W. C. (1976) Propagation of cause in ecosystems. In: Patten, B. C. (ed.), Systems analysis and simulation in ecology, IV. New York: Academic Press. [RS]Google Scholar
Pianka, E. R. (1974) Evolutionary ecology. New York: Harper & Row. [RS]Google Scholar
Pittenger, T., Shaw, R., & Mark, L. (1979) Perceptual information for the age-level of form as a higher-order invariant of growth. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance (in press). [JAF, RS]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Prigogine, I. (1978) Time, structure and fluctuations. Science, 201: 777785. [IRS]CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Putnam, H. (1960) Minds and machines. In: Hook, S. (ed), Dimensions of mind. New York: New York Univ. Press. [JAF]Google Scholar
Putnam, H. (1962) It ain't necessarily so. The Journal of Philosophy 59:658671. [JJK]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, H. (1970) Is semantics possible? Metaphilosophy 1:189201. [JJK]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, H. (1975) The meaning of meaning. In: Cundersen, K. (ed.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science. 7. Language, mind and knowledge. Minneapolis: Univ. of Minnesota Press. [JAF]Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. (1953) Two dogmas of empiricism. From a Logical Point of View, pp. 2046. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard Univ. Press. [JJK]Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. O.(1960) Word and object. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. [JJCS, SPS]Google Scholar
Rosen, R. (1978) Dynamical similarity and the theory of biological transformations. Bulletin of Mathematical Biology, 40:549579. [RS]CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Searle, J.R. (1958) Proper names. Mind 67:166173. [JJK]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Searle, J. R. (1978) Literal meaning. Erkentnis 13:207224. [HLD]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shaw, B., & McIntyre, M. (1974) Algoristic foundations to cognitive psychology. In: Weimer, W., & Palermo, D. (eds.), Cognition and the symbolic processes. Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum. [RS]Google Scholar
Shaw, B., & Turvey, M. T. (in press) Coalitions as models for ecosystems: A realist perspective on perceptual organization. In: Kubovy, M., and Pomerantz, T. (eds.), Perceptual organization. Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum. [RS]Google Scholar
Shaw, B., Turvey, M. T., & Mace, W. (in press) Ecological psychology: The consequence of a commitment to realism. In Weimer, W., and Palermo, D. (eds.), Cognition and the symbolic process, II. Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum. [RS]Google Scholar
Shoemaker, S. (1976) Embodiment and behavior. In: Rorty, A. O. (ed.) The identities of persons, pp. 109137. Berkeley: Univ. of California Press. [LHD]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Soodak, H., & Iberall, A. (1978) Homeokinetics: A physical science for complex system. Science 201:579582. [RS]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stahl, W. R. (1961) Dimensional analysis in mathematical biology. Bulletin of Mathematical Biophysics 23:355376. [RS]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stich, S. P. (1978) Autonomous psychology and the belief-desire thesis. The Monist 61:4. [SPS]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stich, S. P. (1979) Do animals have beliefs? Australasian Journal of Philosophy 57:1. [SPS]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stich, S. P. (forthcoming) On the ascription of content. In: Woodfield, A. (ed), Mental representation and intentional content. [SPS]Google Scholar
Thom, R. (1975) Structural stability and morphogenesis. Reading, Mass.: Benjamin. [RS]Google Scholar
Turvey, M. T., & Shaw, R. (1979) The primacy of perceiving: An ecological reformulation of perception for understanding memory. In: Nilsson, L.-C. (ed), Perspectives on memory research. Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum. [RS]Google Scholar
Wilkes, K. V. (1978) Physicalism. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. [JJCS]Google Scholar
Winograd, T. (1972) Understanding natural language. New York: Academic Press. [EC, JAF]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wittgenstein, . (1961) Tractatus loglco-philosophicus. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. [JJCS]Google Scholar
Wittgenstein., (1969) On certainty. New York: Harper and Row. [HLD]Google Scholar
Yates, F. E. (in press) Physical biology: A basis for modeling living systems. Journal of Cybernetics and Information Science. [RS]Google Scholar
Yates, F. E., Marsh, D. T., & Iberall, A. S. (1972) Integration of the whole organism: A foundation for a theoretical biology, In: Behnke, J. A. (ed), Challenging biological problems: Directions toward their solution. New York: Oxford Univ. Press. [RS]Google Scholar