Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-2lccl Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-25T10:08:07.083Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

THE PROGRESSIVE ERA ASSAULT ON INDIVIDUALISM AND PROPERTY RIGHTSa

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  17 July 2012

James W. Ely Jr.
Affiliation:
Law and History, Vanderbilt University

Abstract

This essay examines the far-reaching attack on individualism and property rights which characterized the Progressive Era of the early twentieth century. Scholars and political figures associated with Progressivism criticized the individualist values of classical liberalism and rejected the traditional notion of limited government espoused by the framers of the Constitution. They expressed great confidence in regulatory agencies, staffed by experts, to effectuate policy. Progressives paved the way for the later triumph of statist ideology with the New Deal in the 1930s.

The essay traces the sources of the Progressive antipathy to individual rights to the influence of Bismarck’s program in Imperial Germany and the Social Gospel theology. It gives attention to the views of leading Progressive intellectuals who stressed the perceived need for increased governmental power and governance by an educated elite. The essay also explores the impact of Progressivism on constitutional law, arguing that the rise of “sociological jurisprudence,” with its skepticism about courts and stress on judicial deference to legislative judgments, served to advance the Progressive political agenda. Progressives looked with disfavor on any constitutional doctrine which curtailed governmental authority. The Progressive movement left a lasting legacy of diminished regard for individualism and a jurisprudence which stripped property of muscular constitutional protection.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Social Philosophy and Policy Foundation 2012

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Gladden, Washington, The New Idolatry and Other Discussions (New York: McClure, Phillips & Co., 1905), 171Google Scholar.

2 Croly, Herbert, The Promise of American Life (Boston: Northeastern University, 1909; reprint, Cosimo, Inc., 2005), 23Google Scholar.

3 Epstein, Richard A., How Progressives Rewrote the Constitution (Washington, D.C.: Cato Institute, 2006), 135Google Scholar.

4 See, e.g., Hofstadter, Richard, The Age of Reform From Bryan to F.D.R. (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1955), 131269Google Scholar; Buenker, John D., Urban Liberalism and Progressive Reform (New York: Scribner, 1973)Google Scholar; Blum, John Morton, The Republican Roosevelt, 2d ed. (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1977)Google Scholar; McGerr, Michael, A Fierce Discontent: The Rise and Fall of the Progressive Movement in America (New York: Oxford University Press, 2003)Google Scholar.

5 Lears, Jackson, Rebirth of A Nation: The Making of Modern America, 1877–1920 (New York: HarperCollins Publishers, 2009)Google Scholar.

6 Hovenkamp, Herbert, “The Mind and Heart of Progressive Legal Thought,” Iowa Law Review, 81 (1995): 157Google Scholar.

7 Graber, Mark A., Transforming Free Speech: The Ambiguous Legacy of Civil Libertarianism (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1991), 7879Google Scholar (“Most prominent early twentieth-century proponents of federal and state economic regulations also supported federal and state speech regulations.”); Rabban, David M., Free Speech in Its Forgotten Years (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1997), 212Google Scholar (noting that Progressives had a limited conception of free speech).

8 McGerr, A Fierce Discontent, supra note 4, at 182–218 (“Progressives seldom contested the increasing division of Americans into separate enclaves.”); Bernstein, David E., Rehabilitating Lochner: Defending Individual Rights Against Progressive Reform (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2011), 78CrossRefGoogle Scholar (“Most Progressive political and intellectual leaders shared the racism of the day and did not support equal rights for African Americans.”).

9 Pickens, Donald K., Eugenics and the Progressives (Nashville: Vanderbilt University Press, 1968), 102–30Google Scholar; Willrich, Michael, “The Two Percent Solution: Eugenic Jurisprudence and the Socialization of American Law, 1900–1930,” Law and History Review, 16 (1998): 63, 64CrossRefGoogle Scholar (“… eugenicists in the Progressive Era were eager to use the full range of state police powers to prevent the reproduction of criminality, deviancy, and dependency.”); Cannato, Vincent J., American Passage: The History of Ellis Island (New York: Harper-Collins, 2009)Google Scholar (discussing the affinity between Progressives and immigration control).

10 Langum, David J., Crossing Over the Line: Legislating Morality and the Mann Act (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994), 6Google Scholar. (Progressives believed that by “the proper use of social engineering, often employing the coercion of the federal government, individual behavior could be controlled and changed through legislation.”); McGerr, A Fierce Discontent, supra note 4, at 81–94 (discussing Progressive campaigns against prostitution and divorce); Schweik, Susan M., The Ugly Laws: Disability in Public (New York: New York University Press, 2009)Google Scholar (discussing municipal ordinances in the Progressive era which banned the appearance of maimed or deformed persons on the streets); Connelly, Mark Thomas, The Response to Prostitution in the Progressive Era (Chapel Hill, N.C.: University of North Carolina Press, 1980), 7Google Scholar (treating efforts to eliminate prostitution during the Progressive era, and concluding that “in one sense anti-prostitution was a progressive reform and, like much of the progressive reform impulse, had its optimistic and confident, not to mention self-righteous, strains”); Schlossman, Steven and Wallach, Stephanie, “The Crime of Precocious Sexuality: Female Juvenile Delinquency ant the Progressive Era,” in Weisberg, D. Kelly, ed., Women and the Law: A Social Historical Perspective (Cambridge, MA: Schenkman Publishing Company, 1982, 2 vols.), vol. IIGoogle Scholar, (detailing Progressive campaign against prostitution and female delinquency).

11 Timberlake, James H., Prohibition and the Progressive Movement, 1900–1920 (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1963), 2CrossRefGoogle Scholar (“… prohibition was actually written into the Constitution as a progressive reform. As an integral part of the Progressive movement, prohibition drew on the same moral idealism and sought to deal with the same basic problems.”). In fact, many conservatives opposed prohibition on grounds that it infringed property rights and enlarged the power of the federal government. Ibid., 176–77. See also, Kersch, Ken I., Constructing Civil Liberties: Discontinuities in the Development of American Constitutional Law (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), 74CrossRefGoogle Scholar (“Prohibition, moreover, like the assertion of regulatory power over other aspects of economic life at the time, was understood as a progressive measure and a full part of the progressive political program.”).

12 Rodgers, Daniel T., “Rights Consciousness in American History,” in Bodenhamer, David J. and Ely, James W. Jr., eds., The Bill of Rights in Modern America, rev. ed. (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2008), 18Google Scholar.

13 Ely, James W. Jr., Railroads and American Law (Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 2001), 225–39Google Scholar; Martin, Albro, Enterprise Denied: Origins of the Decline of American Railroads, 1897–1917 (New York: Columbia University Press, 1971)Google Scholar.

14 Erickson, Nancy S., “Historical Background of ‘Protective’ Labor Legislation: Muller v. Oregon,” in Weisberg, D. Kelly, ed., Women and the Law: The Social Historical Perspective (Cambridge, Mass: Schenkman, 2 vols., 1982), vol. 1, 155–86Google Scholar (stressing that Progressives favored paternalistic legislation that limited employment opportunities for women); Hoff, Joan, Law, Gender, and Injustice: A Legal History of U.S. Women (New York: New York University Press, 1991) 193203Google Scholar. For an expression of the typical Progressive attitude, see Ely, Richard T., Socialism and Social Reform (New York: Thomas Y. Crowell & Co., 1894), 322Google Scholar (“Night work should be prohibited for women and persons under eighteen years of age; and, in particular, all work injurious to the female organism should be forbidden to women.”).

15 Maier, Pauline, American Scripture: Making the Declaration of Independence (New York: Knopf, 1997), 87Google Scholar.

16 Dewey, John, Liberalism and Social Action (New York: C. P. Putnam's Sons, 1935): 16Google Scholar (“The whole temper of [Locke's] philosophy is individualistic in the sense in which individualism is opposed to organized social action.”)

17 Paul, Ellen Frankel, “Freedom of Contract and the ‘Political Economy’ of Lochner v. New York,” NYU Journal of Law & Liberty 1 (2005): 528–37Google Scholar (pointing out that Lockean principles are evident in the Declaration of Independence and the state constitutions of the Revolutionary period).

18 Virginia Constitution of 1776, sec.1.

19 Dellinger, Walter, “The Indivisibility of Economic Rights and Personal Liberty,” Cato Supreme Court Review 2003–2004: 19Google Scholar (“Economic rights, property rights, and personal rights have been joined appropriately, since the time of the founding.”).

20 In 1890, Justice Stephen J. Field declared: “It should never be forgotten that protection to property and to persons cannot be separated. Where property is insecure, the rights of persons are unsafe. Protection to one goes with protection to the other; and there can be neither prosperity nor progress where either is uncertain.” “Centenary of the Supreme Court,” 134 U.S. 729, 745 (1890)Google Scholar.

21 John Dewey, Liberalism and Social Action, supra note 16, at 18.

22 Crouch, Leonard C., “Judicial Tendencies of the Court of Appeals During the Incumbency of Chief Judge Hiscock,” Cornell Law Quarterly 12 (1927): 142Google Scholar.

23 Gillman, Howard, The Constitution Besieged: The Rise and Demise of Lochner Era Police Powers Jurisprudence (Durham: Duke University Press, 1993), 63Google Scholar.

24 Alschuler, Albert W., Law Without Values: The Life, Work, and Legacy of Justice Holmes (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2000), 9, 26Google Scholar.

25 Beard, Charles A., Politics (New York: Columbia University Press, 1908), 31Google Scholar.

26 Under Rousseau's theory of the social contract individuals must surrender all rights to the community and abandon ideas of natural liberty. The community acts “under the supreme direction of the general will” for purposes of “the common good.” Rousseau did not scruple to embrace authoritarian means to achieve his goals. “In order, therefore,” he wrote, “that the social compact may not be a meaningless formality, it includes the tacit agreement, which alone can give force to the rest, that anyone who refuses to obey the general will shall be forced to do so by the whole body; which means nothing more or less than that he will be forced to be free.” Watkins, Frederick, ed., Rousseau—Political Writings (New York: Thomas Nelson and Sons, 1953)Google Scholar.

27 Bellamy, Edward, Looking Backward 2000–1887 (Boston: Tichnor & Co., 1888; reprinted, Matthew Beaumont, ed., New York: Oxford University Press, 2007)Google Scholar.

28 Ibid. at 141.

29 Sadler, Elizabeth, “One Book's Influence: Edward Bellamy's ‘Looking Backward’,” New England Quarterly 17 (1944): 530–55CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

30 Budd v. New York, 143 U.S. 517, 551 (1892)Google Scholar (Brewer, J., dissenting).

31 Eisenach, Eldon J., The Lost Promise of Progressivism (Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 1994), 9294Google Scholar (“By the first decade of the twentieth century the connection between study in Germany and reform in America had become clear.”); Rodgers, Daniel T., Atlantic Crossings: Social Politics in a Progressive Age (Cambridge: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1998), 7689Google Scholar (discussing impact of study in German universities on young Progressive intellectuals); Lears, Rebirth of A Nation, supra note 5, at 198 (“Some Progressive Intellectuals were also profoundly impressed by the welfare-state policies emerging in Berlin and other European centers of social-democratic thought.”). See also Epstein, How Progressives Rewrote the Constitution, supra note 3, at 3 (noting that “Progressives were influenced in part by Bismarckian social initiatives in nineteenth-century Germany”).

32 Croly, The Promise of American Life, supra note 2, at 249–50.

34 In a series of writings Walter Rauschenbusch assailed capitalist society, urged a more egalitarian distribution of wealth, attacked economic competition, and called for public ownership of the means of production. See, e.g., Christianity and the Social Crisis (New York: Macmillan, 1907; reprint Louisville, KY: Westminster/John Knox Press, 1991)Google Scholar Rauschenbusch complained: “Our industrial individualism neutralizes the social consciousness created by Christianity.” Ibid. at 388.

35 Gorrell, Donald K., The Age of Social Responsibility: The Social Gospel in the Progressive Era, 1900–1920 (Macon, GA: Mercer University Press, 1988), 191Google Scholar.

36 Rauschenbusch, Walter, “The Ideals of Social Reformers,” American Journal of Sociology 2 (1892): 202CrossRefGoogle Scholar (“One of the special tasks of our generation is the work of wedding Christianity and the social movement”).

37 Lears, Rebirth of A Nation, supra note 5, at 196–97 (“In fact it was the religious dimension of reform that underwrote its intensity and its virtually limitless scope.”). See Rauschenbusch, Walter, Christianizing the Social Order (New York: Macmillan Company 1912)Google Scholar (urging “socializing property”).

38 Gunther, Gerald, Learned Hand: The Man and the Judge (New York: Albert A. Knopf, 1994), 230Google Scholar (commenting that 1912 Progressive Party convention, which nominated Theodore Roosevelt for president, “had more the air of a religious crusade than a political gathering”); Gorrell, The Age of Social Responsibility, supra note 35, at 182–89 (discussing the number of Social Gospel advocates who actively supported the Progressive Party in 1912).

39 Lears, Rebirth of A Nation, supra note 5, at 352–53 (pointing out that when Progressive ideas reappeared in the 1930s they were presented in secular terms and characterized as “liberal” rather than Progressive). See also Rotunda, Ronald D., The Politics of Language: Liberalism as Word and Symbol (Iowa City: University of Iowa Press, 1986), 14–17, 38–51Google Scholar (discussing how the term “liberal” replaced the older term “progressive” in the 1930s).

40 Gladden, William, “Christian Socialism,” Minutes of the National Council of the Congregational Churches of the United States, October 9–14, 1889 (Boston: Congregational Sunday School and Publishing Company, 1889), 338Google Scholar.

41 Walter Rauschenbusch, “The Ideals of Social Reformers,” supra note 36, at 211.

42 Gladden, The New Idolatry, supra note 1, at 130.

43 Declaration of Principles,” Religious Education 9 (April 1914): 98CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

44 Croly, , Progressive Democracy (New York: Macmillan Company, 1914), 15Google Scholar.

45 Ibid., at 304.

46 Ibid. See Forcey, Charles, The Crossroads of Liberalism: Croly, Weyl, Lippmann, and the Progressive Era, 1900–1925 (New York: Oxford University Press, 1961), 4041Google Scholar (stressing Croly's virtual obsession with executive power to effectuate reform).

47 Croly, The Promise of American Life, supra note 2, at 275.

48 Ibid., at 359.

49 Croly, Progressive Democracy, supra note 44, at 347–77. Croly revealingly contrasted the administrative process and traditional courts: “The administrative court represents a social policy based on a collective social ideal. The common-law judge represents a social policy founded on the protection of individual rights.” Ibid., at 368.

50 Ibid. at 370.

51 Higgs, Robert, Crisis and Leviathan: Critical Episodes in the Growth of American Government (New York: Oxford University Press, 1987), 112Google Scholar. (“Certainly the Progressive Faith in the efficacy of placing ‘experts’ in positions of authority—social engineers to solve social problems—was naïve at best”.)

52 McGerr, A Fierce Discontent, supra note 4, at 217.

53 Hovenkamp, Herbert, Enterprise and American Law, 1836–1937 (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1991), 77CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

54 Forcey, The Crossroads of Liberalism, supra note 46, at 38–40, 43. (“… Croly had an abiding faith in the powerful few.”)

55 Gould, Lewis L., Four Hats In The Ring: The 1912 Election and the Birth of Modern American Politics (Lawrence, Kan.University Press of Kansas, 2008), 182Google Scholar. See also Kornbluh, Mark Lawrence, Why America Stopped Voting: The Decline of Participatory Democracy and the Emergence of Modern American Politics (New York: New York University Press, 2000), 138–60Google Scholar (discussing impact of administrative governance on participation in politics).

56 Stettner, Edward A., Shaping Modern Liberalism: Herbert Croly and Progressive Thought (Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas, 1993), 166Google Scholar.

57 Ibid. at 59–60 (stressing Croly's confidence in a trained bureaucracy).

58 Croly, Progressive Democracy, supra note 44, at 314.

59 Croly, The Promise of American Life, supra note 2, at 209.

60 Ibid. at 209–10. Croly declared that “under a legal system which holds private property sacred there may be equal rights, but there cannot possibly be any equal opportunities for exercising such rights.” Ibid. at 181.

61 Diggins, John P., Mussolini and Fascism: The View from America (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1972), 204–5, 228–31Google Scholar. Croly, of course, was not the only Progressive intellectual to initially look with favor upon Italian fascism. But see Stettner, Shaping Modern Liberalism, supra note 56, at 155–57 (disputing contention that Croly was sympathetic to fascism).

62 Rader, Benjamin G., The Academic Mind and Reform: The Influence of Richard T. Ely in American Life (Lexington, KY: University of Kentucky Press, 1966), 166Google Scholar.

63 Quandt, Jean B., “Religion and Social Thought: The Secularization of Postmillennialism,” American Quarterly 25 (1973): 402–3CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Hovenkamp, Enterprise and American Law, supra note 53, at 101. (“the economics of Progressives such as Ely contained a good deal of religious moralizing that proved unacceptable to more positivist economists in the 1930s and after.”)

64 Quandt, “Religion and Social Thought,” supra note 63, at 403.

65 Ely, Richard T., Property and Contract in Their Relations to the Distribution of Wealth (New York: Macmillan Company, 1914, 2 vols.)Google Scholar, vol. I at 165–90 (property), II at 615–18 (contract).

66 Rader, The Academic Mind and Reform, supra note 62, at 103.

67 Ely, Richard T., Socialism and Social Reform (New York: Thomas Y. Crowell & Co., 1894), 253–54Google Scholar; Rader, The Academic Mind and Reform, supra note 62, at 102–3.

68 Rader, The Academic Mind and Reform, supra note 62, at 104–5.

69 Ibid., at 235.

70 Thies, Clifford F. and Pecquet, Gary M., “The Shaping of a Future President's Economic Thought: Richard T. Ely and Woodrow Wilson at ‘The Hopkins’,” The Independent Review 15 (2010): 267–75Google Scholar.

71 Forcey, The Crossroads of Liberalism, supra note 46, at 169, 185–86.

72 Wilson, Woodrow, The New Freedom (New York: Doubleday, Page & Co., 1913, reprint 1919), 286Google Scholar.

73 Wilson, Woodrow, The State (Boston: D.C. Heath, 1889, rev. ed. Boston: D.C. Heath, 1901), 621Google Scholar.

74 Ibid., at 623.

75 Ibid., at 631.

76 Ibid., at 632.

77 Wilson, The New Freedom, supra note 72, at 284.

78 Woodrow Wilson to Hermann Eduard von Holst, June 29, 1893, in Link, Arthur S., ed. The Papers of Woodrow Wilson, vol. 8 (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1970), 271Google Scholar.

79 Wilson, The New Freedom, supra note 72, at 47.

80 Ibid., at 39.

81 Link, ed., The Papers of Woodrow Wilson, vol. 5, supra note 78, at 69. See also Thomas, George, The Madisonian Constitution (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Press, 2008), 6569Google Scholar (examining Wilson's dislike of the separation of powers doctrine, and desire to reconstruct constitutional authority to effectuate popular will).

82 LaFollette, Robert M., Introduction to Gilbert E. Roe, Our Judicial Oligarchy (New York: Huebsch, 1912), vGoogle Scholar.

83 Roosevelt, Theodore, “Judges and Progress,” Outlook 100 (January 6, 1912): 42Google Scholar.

84 Mayer, David N., Liberty of Contract: Rediscovering a Lost Constitutional Right (Washington, DC: Cato Institute, 2011) 6Google Scholar.

85 Ibid. at 115 (pointing out that judicial invocation of laissez-faire principles “would have resulted in the overturning of literally hundreds of laws that the Court upheld as valid exercises of the police power”).

86 Ely, James W. Jr., The Guardian of Every Other Right: A Constitutional History of Property Rights, 3d ed. (New York: Oxford University Press, 2008), 108–9Google Scholar.

87 198 U.S. 45 (1905). For assessments of this important case, see David E. Bernstein, Rehabilitating Lochner, supra note 8 ; Strauss, David A.,” Why Was Lochner Wrong?, University of Chicago Law Review 70 (2003): 373CrossRefGoogle Scholar; David N. Mayer, Liberty of Contract, supra note 84, at 70–76.

88 Bernstein, David E., “Lochner Era Revisionism, Revised: Lochner and the Origins of Fundamental Rights Constitutionalism,” Georgetown Law Journal 92 (2003): 29Google Scholar (criticizing historians of the Progressive and New Deal eras for tailoring constitutional history to serve political objectives).

89 Ross, William G., A Muted Fury: Populists, Progressives, and Labor Unions Confront the Supreme Court, 1890–1937 (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1994), 4969Google Scholar (discussing Progressive denunciation of judicial review as a usurpation of power).

90 Ibid., at 110–29.

91 Theodore Roosevelt, “Judges and Progress,” supra note 83, at 46; New York Times, February 22, 1912Google Scholar; “A Charter of Democracy”, in Roosevelt, Theodore, Social Justice and Popular Rule (New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1926), 119Google Scholar: Ross, A Muted Fury, supra note 89, at 130–54. See also, Lewis, William Draper, “The Recall of Judicial Decisions,” Proceedings of the Academy of Political Science 37 (1913): 37CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

92 Hofstadter, Richard, The Progressive Historians: Turner, Beard, Parrington (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1968), 182206Google Scholar.

93 Beard, Charles A., An Economic Interpretation of the Constitution of the United States (New York: Macmillan Company, 1913), 324Google Scholar.

94 Hofstadter, The Progressive Historians, supra note 92, at 218.

95 Murphy, Paul L., “Holmes, Brandeis, and Pound: Sociological Jurisprudence as a Response to Economic Laissez-Faire,” in Paul, Ellen Frankel and Dickman, Howard, eds., Liberty, Property, and Government: Constitutional Interpretation Before the New Deal (Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 1989), 5660Google Scholar; Bernstein, Rehabilitating Lochner, supra note 8, at 42–47.

96 Pound's vigorous assault on the liberty of contract doctrine is quite curious. In fact, the doctrine was rarely invoked by the Supreme Court. Alexander, Gregory S., “The Limits of Freedom of Contract in the Age of Laissez-Faire Constitutionalism,” in Buckley, Francis H., ed., The Fall and Rise of Freedom of Contract (Durham, N.C.: Duke University, 1999)Google Scholar (“… even during the period between 1885 and 1930, the supposed height of laissez-faire constitutionalism, the courts, federal and state, did not uniformly sustain the liberty of contract principle.”); Hall, Kermit L. and Karsten, Peter, The Magic Mirror: Law in American History, 2d ed. (New York: Oxford University Press, 2009), 264Google Scholar (“The Lochner decision was in many ways an aberration with limited impact.”). This raises a serious question of whether Pound was simply tilting at windmills.

97 Pound, Roscoe, “Mechanical Jurisprudence,” Columbia Law Review 8 (1908): 616CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

98 198 U.S. at 75–76.

99 Consider the jurisprudence of Justice Rufus W. Peckham, the author the majority opinion in Lochner. See Ely, James W. Jr, “Rufus W. Peckham and Economic Liberty,” Vanderbilt Law Review 62 (2009): 637Google Scholar (“Even a glance at Peckham's opinions makes it evident that he was not engaged in abstract deduction from legal principles and precedents. Instead, Peckham championed what he regarded as socially desirable outcomes in defense of property rights and contractual freedom. Peckham cannot fairly be described as a legal formalist.”).

100 Ely, James W. Jr., The Chief Justiceship of Melville W. Fuller, 1888–1910 (Columbia, SC: University of South Carolina Press, 1995), 73–74, 83–149Google Scholar.

101 Pound, Roscoe, “The Scope and Purpose of Sociological Jurisprudence,” Harvard Law Review 25 (1911): 146–47CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

102 Pound, “Sociological Jurisprudence” supra note 100, part III, (1913): 512–13.

103 Ibid. at 515.

104 Pound, “Mechanical Jurisprudence,” supra note 97, at 621.

105 Pound, Roscoe, “Liberty of Contract,” Yale Law Journal 18 (1909): 464CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

106 See Leuchtenburg, William E., The Supreme Court Reborn: Constitutional Revolution in the Age of Roosevelt (New York: Oxford University Press, 1995), 19Google Scholar (calling attention to Holmes's “disdain for facts”).

107 Pound, “Liberty of Contract,” supra note 105, at 457,

108 Learned Hand to Van Vechten Veeder, December 11, 1913, as quoted in Gunther, Gerald, Learned Hand: The Man and the Judge (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1994), 211Google Scholar.

109 Beard, Politics, supra note 25, at 29.

110 Tamanaha, Brian Z., Beyond the Formalist-Realist Divide: The Role of Politics in Judging (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2010, 2443Google Scholar (“… contrary to what Pound and others have asserted, lawyers, academics, and judges at the time did not widely believe that judging was an exercise in mechanical deduction”). See also Alschuler, Law Without Values, supra note 24, at 91–100 (rejecting notion that judges in the nineteenth century adhered to mechanical jurisprudence, and insisting that judges adapted law to meet changing circumstances).

111 Bernstein, Rehabilitating Lochner, supra note 8, at 41 (“… the Progressive legal elites' support for ‘sociological jurisprudence’ often masked a political agenda that favored a significant increase in government involvement in American economic and social life”).

112 Horwitz, Morton J., The Transformation of American Law, 1870–1960: The Crisis of Legal Orthodoxy (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992), 7Google Scholar: (“Although in every other field of American history, Progressive historiography, premised on a conflict between the “people” and the “interests” has been overthrown as simplistic, in the constitutional history of the Lochner era it has continued to be the standard mode of explanation.”)

113 Ibid.

114 Brandeis, Louis D., “The Living Law,” Illinois Law Review 10 (1916): 464Google Scholar.

115 In addition to Lochner, Brandeis singled out Ives v. South Buffalo Railway Co., 201 N.Y. 271 (1911) (invalidating New York's workers' compensation law) and Adair v. United States, 208 U.S. 161 (1908) (striking down on liberty of contract doctrine a congressional measure outlawing so-called yellow dog contacts). These were favorite targets of the Progressives.

116 Keedy, Edwin R., “The Decline of Traditionalism and Individualism,” University of Pennsylvania Law Review 65 (1916): 772Google Scholar.

117 House, Edward Mandell, Philip Dru Administrator: A Story of Tomorrow 1920–1935 (New York: B. W. Huebach, 1912, reprinted Memphis, Tenn.: General Books, 2010)Google Scholar. Philip Dru has received surprisingly little attention from scholars. For exceptions, see Lears, Rebirth of A Nation, supra note 5, at 330–31; Bloomfield, Maxwell, “Constitutional Ideology and Progressive Fiction,” Journal of American Culture 18 (1995): 34Google Scholar. See also a review of this work by Lippman, Walter, “America's Future,” New York Times, December 8, 1912Google Scholar.

118 For the close relationship between Wilson and House, see Link, Arthur S., Woodrow Wilson and the Progressive Era, 1910–1917 (New York: Harper & Row, 1954), 26Google Scholar.

119 Leuchtenburg, William E., “Progressivism and Imperialism: The Progressive Movement and American Foreign Policy, 1898–1916,” Mississippi Valley Historical Review 39 (1952): 483504CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

120 Link, Woodrow Wilson and the Progressive Era, supra note 118, at 81–114 (discussing Wilson's extensive interventions in Caribbean nations and Mexico, and noting that Wilson was “dedicated to the democratic ideal, at least theoretically, and obsessed with the concept of America's mission in the world.”).

121 Root, Elihu, Experiments in Government and the Essentials of the Constitution (Princeton: Princeton University Press, (1913), 3Google Scholar.

122 Ibid. at 43, 44, 53, 62–63, 75.

123 Hofstadter, The Age of Reform, supra note 4, at 273 (“Participation in the war put an end to the Progressive movement.”); McGerr, A Fierce Discontent, supra note 4, at 299–313.

124 Mencken, H. L., Baltimore Sun, January 19, 1926Google Scholar.