Hostname: page-component-7c8c6479df-p566r Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-03-29T04:44:41.127Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Rights, Indirect Utilitarianism, and Contractarianism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 December 2008

Alan P. Hamlin
Affiliation:
The University, Southampton, England

Extract

Economic approaches to both social evaluation and decision-making are typically Paretian or utilitarian in nature and so display commitments to both welfarism and consequentialism. The contrast between the economic approach and any rights-based social philosophy has spawned a large literature that may be divided into two branches. The first is concerned with the compatibility of rights and utilitarianism (or Pare-tianism) seen as independent moral forces (e.g., the debate on the possibility of a Paretian liberal). This branch of the literature may be characterized as an example of the broader debate between the teleological and deontological approaches. The second is concerned with the possibility that substantial rights may be grounded in utilitarianism (or Pare-tianism) with the moral force of rights being derived from more basic commitments to welfarism and consequentialism. This branch of the literature may be characterized as an exploration of the flexibility of the teleological approach, and, in particular, its ability to give rise to views more normally associated with the deontological approach. This essay is concerned with the second branch of the literature.

Type
Essays
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1989

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

d'Aspremont, C., and Gevers, L. 1977. “Equity and the Informational Basis of Collective Choice.” Review of Economic Studies 44:199209.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchanan, J. M. 1975. The Limits of Liberty. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. 1977. Taking Rights Seriously. London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
Elster, J. 1983. Sour Grapes. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elster, J. 1984. Ulysses and the Sirens, Revised edition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Feinberg, J. 1970. “The Nature and Value of Rights.” Journal of Value Enquiry 4:243–57. Reprinted in Feinberg, 1980.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gauthier, . 1978. “Voluntary Euthanasia and the Inalienable Right to Life.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 7:93123. Reprinted in Feinberg, 1980.Google Scholar
Gauthier, . 1980. Rights, Justice and the Bounds of Liberty. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Gauthier, D. 1986. Morals by Agreement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gibbard, A. 1984. “Utilitarianism and Human Rights.” In Human Rights, edited by Paul, E. F., Miller, F. D., and Paul, J., pp. 92102. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Gray, J. 1984. “Indirect Utility and Fundamental Rights.” In Human Rights, edited by Paul, E. F., Miller, F. D., and Paul, J., pp. 7391. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Gray, J. 1989. “Contractarian Method, Private Property and the Market Economy.” Nomos 31. Forthcoming.Google Scholar
Griffin, J. 1984. “Towards a Substantive Theory of Rights.” In Utility and Rights, edited by Frey, R. G., pp. 137–60. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Griffin, J. 1986. Well-Being. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hamlin, A. P. 1986. Ethics, Economics and the State. Brighton: Wheatsheaf Books.Google Scholar
Hamlin, A. 1989. “Liberty, Contract and the State.” In The Good Polity, edited by Hamlin, A. P. and Pettit, P., pp. 87101. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hamlin, A. P., and Pettit, P. 1989. “Normative Analysis of the State: Some Preliminaries.” In The Good Polity, edited by Hamlin, A. P. and Pettit, P., pp. 113. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hare, R. M. 1981. Moral Thinking. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hare, R. 1984. “Rights, Utility and Universalizacion, Reply to J. L. Mackie.” In Utility and Rights, edited by Frey, R. G., pp. 106–20. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Harsanyi, J. 1985a. “Does Reason Tell Us What Moral Code to Follow and, Indeed, to Follow Any Moral Code at All?Ethics 96:4255.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harsanyi, J. 1985b. “Rule Utilitarianism, Equality and Justice.” In Ethics and Economics, edited by Paul, E. F., Miller, F. D., and Paul, J., pp. 115–27. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Lyons, D. 1980. “Utility as a Possible Ground of Rights.” Nous 14:1728.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lyons, D. 1982. “Utility and Rights.” Nomos 24:107–38.Google Scholar
Mackie, J. L. 1984. “Rights, Utility, and Universalization.” In Utility and Rights, edited by Frey, R. G., pp. 86105. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Narveson, J. 1984. “Contractarian Rights.” In Utility and Rights, edited by Frey, R. G., pp. 161–74. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Nozick, R. 1974. Anarchy, State and Utopia. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Parfit, D. 1984. Reasons and Persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pettit, P. 1986. “Can the Welfare State Take Rights Seriously?” In Law, Rights and the Welfare State, edited by Galligan, D. and Sampford, C.. London: Croom Helm.Google Scholar
Pettit, D. 1987. “Rights, Constraints and Trumps.” Analysis 46:814.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pettit, D. 1988. “The Consequentialist Can Recognise Rights.” Philosophical Quartesrly 38:4255.Google Scholar
Pettit, P., and Brennan, G. 1986. “Restrictive Consequentialism.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 64:438–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rawls, J. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Regan, D. H. 1980. Utilitarianism and Cooperation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Riley, J. 1986. “Generalised Social Welfare Functional: Welfarism, Morality and Liberty.” Social Choice and Welare 3:233–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roberts, K. W. S. 1980. “Interpersonal Comparability and Social Choice Theory.” Review of Economic Studies 47:421–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rowley, C., and Peacock, A. 1975. Welfare Economics: A Liberal Restatement. Oxford: Martin Robertson.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. 1982. “Contractualism and Utilitarianism.” In Utilitarianism and Beyond, edited by Sen, A. K. and Williams, B. A. O.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Schelling, T. C. 1960. The Strategy of Conflict. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Sen, A. K. 1970. “The Impossibility of a Paretian Liberal.” Journal of Political Economy 78:152–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sen, A. K. 1976. “Liberty, Unanimity and Rights.” Economica 43:217–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sen, A. K. 1979a. “Utilitarianism and Welfarism.” Journal of Philosophy 76:463–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sen, A. K. 1979b. “Personal Utilities and Public Judgments: Or What's Wrong with Welfare Economics.” Economic Journal 89:537–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sen, A. K. 1981. “Plural Utility.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 81:193215.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sen, A. K. 1982. “Rights and Agency.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 11:339.Google Scholar
Sen, A. K. 1983. “Liberty and Social Choice.” Journal of Philosophy 80:528.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sen, A. K. 1985. “Well-being, Agency and Freedom.” Journal of Philosophy 82:169221.Google Scholar
Sen, A. K. 1987. On Ethics and, Economics. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Sen, A. K., and Williams, B. A. O. (editors). 1982. Utilitarianism and Beyond. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sugden, R. 1986. The Economics of Rights, Co-operation and Welfare. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Sumner, L. W. 1987. The Moral Foundation of Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Williams, B. A. O. 1973. “A Critique of Utilitarianism.” In Utilitarianism For and Against, edited by Smart, J. J. C. and Williams, B. A. O., pp. 77150. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar