Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-qsmjn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-17T00:11:34.377Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Coaxing Climate Policy Leadership

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  21 December 2012

Abstract

The United States and China have recently been called upon to exercise more leadership in developing an effective international policy response to climate change, but without giving attention to either the risks inherent in taking on such a role or the mechanism by which leading can mobilize others to act in response. Here, I understand leadership as action by a sufficiently powerful actor in a cooperative scheme that is capable of triggering reciprocal actions by followers on behalf of that scheme, and argue that such leadership can be coaxed by potential followers through pledges of reciprocal action that are made conditional upon prior action undertaken by a leader. In the context of the current international impasse over post-Kyoto climate change mitigation commitments, I identify means by which leadership by the U.S. or China might be induced by such conditional pledges, potentially allowing some obstacles to international collective action on climate change mitigation to be overcome.

Type
Special Section: Safeguarding Fairness in Global Climate Governance
Copyright
Copyright © Carnegie Council for Ethics in International Affairs 2012

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

NOTES

1 Jeffrey Marlow, “E.U. Looks to U.S. for Climate Leadership,” New York Times (online edition), June 3, 2009.

2 Elisabeth Rosenthal, “UN Chief Seeks More Climate Change Leadership,” New York Times (online edition), November 18, 2007.

3 Karlsson et al. examine the “demand side” of climate policy leadership by surveying perceptions of potential leaders but stop short of proposing strategies for inducing such leadership. See Karlsson, Christer et al. , “Looking for Leaders: Perceptions of Climate Change Leadership among Climate Change Negotiation Participants,” Global Environmental Politics 11, no. 1 (2011), pp. 89107CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

4 See, e.g., Krosnick, Jon A. and Kinder, Donald R., “Altering the Foundations of Support for the President through Priming,” American Political Science Review 84, no. 2 (1990), pp. 497512CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

5 Shue, Henry, “Face Reality? After You!—A Call for Leadership on Climate Change,” Ethics & International Affairs 25, no. 1 (2011), p. 17CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

6 See, e.g., Repetto, Robert, America's Climate Problem: The Way Forward (New York: Routledge, 2011)Google Scholar. Also, see notes 1 and 2.

7 Shue, “Face Reality?” pp. 19–20.

8 See Vanderheiden, Steve, “Leadership, Moral Authority, and Global Climate Change,” in Hicks, D. A. and Williamson, T., eds., Leadership and Global Justice (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2012), pp. 8082Google Scholar.

9 Hall, Rodney Bruce, “Moral Authority as a Power Resource,” International Organization 51, no. 4 (1997), p. 597CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

10 Parsons, Talcott, Sociological Theory and Modern Society (New York: Free Press, 1967), p. 308Google Scholar.

11 United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change, art. 3, principle 1 (New York: United Nations, 1992).

12 Gardiner, Stephen M., A Perfect Moral Storm: The Ethical Tragedy of Climate Change (New York: Oxford University Press, 2011), chap. 1CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

13 U.S. Department of Energy, Carbon Dioxide Information Analysis Center; cdiac.ornl.gov/.

14 Hardin, Garrett, “The Tragedy of the Commons,” Science 162, no. 3859 (1968), pp. 1243–48Google ScholarPubMed.

15 After specifically naming China, India, Mexico, and Brazil among developing countries excluded from binding emissions targets under Kyoto Protocol terms, the Senate resolved that “the United States should not be a signatory to any protocol to, or other agreement regarding, the United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change of 1992, at negotiations in Kyoto in December 1997, or thereafter, which would (A) mandate new commitments to limit or reduce greenhouse gas emissions for the Annex I Parties, unless the protocol or other agreement also mandates new specific scheduled commitments to limit or reduce greenhouse gas emissions for Developing Country Parties within the same compliance period, or (B) would result in serious harm to the economy of the United States.” In defending his 2001 decision to formally withdraw from the protocol, President George W. Bush echoed the same two concerns.

16 Goodin, Robert E., “Excused by the Unwillingness of Others?” Analysis 72, no. 1 (2012), pp. 1824CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

17 Ibid., p. 24.

18 As I have argued elsewhere, fair terms of cooperation are essential features of an effective climate treaty as necessary conditions for all parties to voluntarily accept their roles in it. See Vanderheiden, Steve, Atmospheric Justice: A Political Theory of Climate Change (New York: Oxford University Press, 2008)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Here, one might add that unfair terms also diminish the moral authority of leadership wielded on behalf of initiating such a treaty framework.

19 Arneson, Richard J., “The Principle of Fairness and Free-Rider Problems,” Ethics 92, no. 4 (1982), pp. 622–23CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

20 This analysis considers the incentive effects of merely pledged reciprocal cooperation, though not of conditional commitments to increase efforts if others join in the cooperative scheme. Underval et al. have modeled the effects of the EU making a conditional commitment to cutting its emissions by 30 percent rather than the 20 percent to which it has already committed, and found that such a commitment would significantly lower the costs for other nations (the United States, Japan, India, and China) to respond with stronger reciprocal commitments, even if it could not guarantee such a result. See Underdal, Arild et al. , “Can Conditional Commitments Break the Climate Negotiations Deadlock?” International Political Science Review 33, no. 4 (2012), pp. 475–93CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

21 The EU, for example, has unconditionally pledged a 20 percent reduction from its 1990 emissions by 2020, but has conditionally promised a 30 percent reduction by that date if other developed countries take on similar commitments. Likewise, Australia has unconditionally committed to a 5 percent reduction from 2000 emissions by 2020, but conditionally committed to a 25 percent reduction if a global climate agreement is reached that stabilizes atmospheric carbon at 450 ppm or lower, and to a 15 percent reduction if that agreement falls short of the 450 ppm target. Copenhagen Accord, Appendix 1; unfccc.int/meetings/copenhagen_dec_2009/items/5264.php.

22 Ward, Hugh, “Game Theory and the Politics of the Global Commons,” Journal of Conflict Resolution 37, no. 2 (1993), p. 229CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

23 Ibid., p. 230.

24 Shue, “Face Reality?” p. 23.

25 See, e.g., Oberthür, Sebastian, “Global Climate Governance after Cancun: Options for EU Leadership,” International Spectator 46, no. 1 (2011), pp. 513CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Kilian, Bertil and Elgström, Ole, “Still a Green Leader? The European Union's Role in International Climate Negotiations,” Cooperation and Conflict 45, no. 3 (2010), pp. 255–73CrossRefGoogle Scholar.