Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-qsmjn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-19T15:26:13.080Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Eclipse of the Individual in Policy (Where is the Place for Justice?)

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 July 2009

Mark J. Bliton
Affiliation:
Assistant Professor of Medical Ethics, Assistant Professor of Philosophy, and Chief of the Clinical Ethics Consultation Service at the Center for Clinical and Research Ethics, Vanderbilt University Medical Center, Nashville, Tennessee.
Stuart G. Finder
Affiliation:
Assistant Professor of Medical Ethics, Assistant Professor of Philosophy, and Associate Director of the Center for Clinical and Research Ethics, Vanderbilt University Medical Center, Nashville, Tennessee.

Extract

Several inquires about healthcare over the past several decades have shown that the evolution of healthcare practices exhibit their own microcosm of local and political influences. Likewise, other studies have shown clearly the ways in which both external and internal institutional factors establish the sectors within which healthcare is delivered. Although restrictions have always been present in some form, it seems obvious that whatever the precise form of healthcare delivery that results from current changes in its organization, there are going to be broader restrictions not only on the choices that providers will be able to make about individual patients' care and needs, but also regarding the character of their clinical judgments. Indeed, there are already reports of instances where physicians' contracts with managed care organizations forbid them to disclose the existence of services not covered by a plan.

Type
Special Section: Can Justice Endure Healthcare Reform?: From Patient Care to Policy (and Back Again)
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1996

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Notes

1. Millman, M. The Unkindest Cut: Life in the Backrooms of Medicine. New York: William Morrow and Company, Inc., 1977.Google Scholar

2. Waitzkin, H. The Politics of Medical Encounters: How Patients and Doctors Deal with Social Problems. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1991.Google Scholar

3. Starr, P. The Social Transformation of American Medicine. New York: Basic Books, Inc., 1982.Google ScholarPubMed

4. Friedson, E. Profession of Medicine: A Study of the Sociology of Applied Knowledge. New York: Harpers & Row, Publishers Inc., 1970.Google Scholar

5. Mechanic, D. Inescapable Decisions: The Imperatives of Health Reform. New Brunswick, N.J.: Transaction Publishers, 1994. See, in particular, Chapter 3, Professional judgment and the rationing of medical care, pp. 6997.Google Scholar

6. Kassirer, JP. Managed care and the morality of the marketplace. New England Journal of Medicine 1995; 333:50.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

7. Veath, RM. A Theory of Medical Ethics. New York: Basic Books, Inc., 1981.Google Scholar

8. Kestenbaum, V, Ed. The Humanity of the III: Phenomenological Perspectives. Knoxville, Tennessee: The University of Tennessee Press, 1982.Google Scholar

9. Engelhardt, HT Jr. The Foundations of Bioethics. New York: Oxford University Press, 1986.Google ScholarPubMed

10. Pellegrino, E, Thomasma, D. For the Patient's Good: The Restoration of Beneficence in Health Care. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

11. Pellegrino, ED. The metamorphosis of medical ethics: a 300-year retrospective. Journal of the American Medical Association 1993; 269:1162.Google Scholar

12. Luce, JM. Physicians do not have a responsibility to provide futile or unreasonable care if a patient or family insists. Critical Care Medicine 1995; 23:760–6.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

13. Lindorff, D. Marketplace Medicine: The Rise of For-Profit Hospital Chains. New York: Bantam Books, 1992:18.Google Scholar

14. The presentation of other as stranger has important epistemic as well as moral ramifications, in relation to both individuals and as anonymous members of various social institutions. Edward Tiryakian explained that point: “At the interpersonal level the stranger is par excellence the other, the non-self, who makes us aware of ourselves by indicating the boundaries of selfhood. The stranger brings us into contact with the limits of ourselves … At the collective level, stranger groups constitute the same challenge to the organized community.” Tiryakian, EA. Sociological perspectives on the stranger. Soundings 1973;56:57.Google Scholar

15. See Shelp, E, Ed. Justice and Health Care. Dordrecht and Boston: D. Reidel Publishing Co., 1981.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

16. Churchill, LR. Rationing Health Care in America: Perceptions and Principles of Justice. Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press, 1987.Google Scholar

17. Daniels, N. Just Health Care. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

18. Morriem, EH. Balancing Act: The New Medical Ethics of Medicine's New Economics. Dordrecht and Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1991.Google Scholar

19. Brennan, TA. Just Doctoring: Medical Ethics in the Liberal State. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1991.Google Scholar

20. As Richard Zaner suggests in his contribution to this Special Section, this was particularly true within the Hippocratic tradition. See, Justice and the individual in the Hippocratic tradition, pp. 511–518.

21. See note 9. Engelhardt, 1986:44–5.Google Scholar

22. Authors as diverse as Mark Siegler and Richard Zaner have heralded the need for change in our understanding and practice of clinical ethics. Both have attempted to shift the discussion about clinical ethics away from the abstractions of philosophical ethics toward the specific relationships found in clinical encounters. See Siegler, M. A legacy of Osier: teaching clinical ethics at the bedside. Journal of the American Medical Association 1978; 239:951–6.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

23. Siegler, M. The doctor-patient encounter and its relationship to theories of health and disease. In: Caplan, AL, Engelhardt, HT Jr, McCartney, JJ, Eds. Concepts of Health and Disease: Interdisciplinary Perspectives. Reading, Massachusetts: Addison-Wesley Publishing Co., 1981:627–44.Google Scholar

24. Zaner, RM. Ethics and the Clinical Encounter. Engelwood Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice-Hall, 1988.Google ScholarPubMed

25. Zaner, RM. Experience and moral life: a phenomenological approach to bioethics. In: DuBose, ER, Hamel, RP, O'Connell, LJ, Eds. A Matter of Principles? Ferment in U.S. Bioethics. Valley Forge, Pennsylvania: Trinity Press International, 1994:211–39.Google Scholar

26. Cassell, EJ: The Nature of Suffering and the Goals of Medicine. New York: Oxford University Press, 1991:179–86.Google Scholar

27. Pellegrino, ED. The healing relationship: the architectonics of clinical medicine. In: Shelp, EE, Ed. The Clinical Encounter: The Moral Fabric of the Physician Patient Relationship. Dordrecht and Boston: D. Reidel Publishing Co., 1983:163–5.Google Scholar

28. See note 24. Zaner, 1988:6971, 105.Google Scholar

29. Cassell, EJ. Talking with Patients, vol. 1. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press, 1985:6.Google Scholar

30. Zaner, RM. Medicine and dialogue. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 1990; 15:308.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

31. Paget, MA. The Unity of Mistakes: A Phenomenological Interpretation of Medical Work. Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1988:53.Google Scholar

32. Apostle, HG (trans.) Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics. Grinnell, Iowa: The Peripatetic Press, 1984:1104a4–5.Google Scholar

33. See note 32. Apostle, 1984:1134b29–30.Google Scholar

34. Schutz, A, Luckman, T. Structures of the Life-World. Trans. Zaner, RM, Engelhardt, HT Jr, Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press, 1973:73–9.Google Scholar

35. See note 34. Schutz, and Luckman, 1973:235–41.Google Scholar

36. See note 27. Pellegrino, 1983:163–5.Google Scholar

37. See Jecker, NS. Caring for “socially undesirable” patients. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 1996;5:500510.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

38. See note 18. Morriem, 1991:56.Google Scholar

39. See note 18. Morriem, 1991:56.Google Scholar

40. See note 5. Mechanic, 1994:82–3.Google Scholar

41. See note 18. Morriem, 1991:56.Google Scholar

42. See note 18. Morriem, 1991:57.Google Scholar

43. Toulmin, S. The tyranny of principles. Hastings Center Report 1981;11(6):3132.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

44. Jonsen, AR. Casuistry and clinical ethics. Theoretical Medicine 1986;7:7172.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

45. Jonsen, AR, Toulmin, S. The Abuse of Casuistry: A History of Moral Reasoning. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1988:vii,1619, 264–5.Google Scholar

46. See note 45. Jonsen, and Toulmin, 1988:306.Google Scholar

47. Arras, JD. Getting down to cases: the revival of casuistry in bioethics. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 1991; 16:2951.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

48. Wildes, KWM. The priesthood of bioethics and the return of casuistry. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 1993; 18:3349.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

49. Tomlinson, T. Casuistry in medical ethics: rehabilitated, or repeat offender? Theoretical Medicine 1994;15(1):520.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

50. Kopelman, LM. Case method and casuistry: the problem of bias. Theoretical Medicine 1994;15(1):2137.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

51. See note 45. Jonsen, and Toulmin, 1988:36,40.Google Scholar

52. See note 45. Jonsen, and Toulmin, 1988:29,68,299.Google Scholar

53. Toulmin, S. Casuistry and clinical ethics. In: DuBose, ER, Hamel, RP, O'Connell, LR. A Matter of Principles? Ferment in U.S. Bioethics. Valley Forge, Pennsylvania: Trinity Press International, 1994:310–8.Google Scholar

54. This insight, in its historical lineage, was secured by the ancient “skeptical” physicians. Ludwig Edelstein cites Sextus Empricus, where Sextus says, “Medicine, however, does not do the same things now and in the next moment; it acts differently in regard to the same individual and its actions are opposed to one another.” Edelstein, L. Ancient Medicine. Tempkin, CL (trans.). Baltimore; Johns Hopkins University Press, 1967:199.Google Scholar

55. Here we must simply acknowledge that much depends on the casuist's employment of the term ‘practical reason.’ However, we do not have the space to pursue that discussion here. Although not necessarily addressing that complex issue, others have published views that coincide with our concern for the complexity of ‘practical reason.’ See note 47. Arras, 1991;Google Scholar note 24. Zaner, 1988;Google Scholar note 49. Tomlinson, 1994;Google Scholar and note 50. Kopelman, 1994.Google Scholar

56. Pellegrino, ED. The anatomy of clinical judgment: some notes on right reason and right action. In: Engelhardt, HT Jr, Spicker, SF, Towers, B. Clinical Judgment: A Critical Appraisal. Dordrecht and Boston: D. Reidel Publishing Co., 1979:169–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

57. See John, Lantos's contribution to this Special Section. Lantos, J. Seeking justice for Priscilla, pp. 485492.Google Scholar

58. Carse, A. Justice within intimate spheres. Journal of Clinical Ethics 1993; 4(1):69.Google ScholarPubMed

59. Jecker, NS, Berg, AO. Allocating medical resources in rural America: alternative perceptions of justice. Social Science and Medicine 1992; 34:471.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

60. Jameton, A. Casuist or Cassandra? Two conceptions of the bioethicist's role. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 1994;3:457.Google ScholarPubMed

61. See note 58. Carse, 1993:69.Google Scholar

62. Hauerwas, S, Burrell, D. From system to story: an alternative pattern for rationality in ethics. In: Hauerwas, S, Jones, LG, Eds. Why Narrative? Readings in Narrative Theology. Grand Rapids, Michigan: William B. Eerdmans Publishing Co., 1977:171.Google Scholar

63. Dallmayr, F. Hermeneutics and justice. In: Wright, K, Ed. Festivals of Interpretation: Essays on HansGeorge Gadamer's Work. Albany, N.Y.: State University of New York Press, 1990:9394.Google Scholar

64. See note 20. Zaner, 1996:514–5.Google Scholar

65. For an important, although not exhaustive, list of various institutional and personal sources of power see Lynch, A. … Has knowledge of (interpersonal) facilitation techniques and theory; has the ability to facilitate (interpersonally)… In: Baylis, FE, Ed. The Health Care Ethics Consultant. Totowa, New Jersey: Humana Press, 1994:5253.Google Scholar

66. See note 24. Zaner, 1988:244.Google Scholar

67. See, for instance, Bayer, A. Ethics, politics, and access to health care: a critical analysis of the President's Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine and Biomedical Research. Cardozo Law Review 1984;6:303–20.Google Scholar

68. Post, SG. Justice, community dialogue, and health care. Journal of Social Philosophy 1992;23(3):2324.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

69. Engelhardt, HT Jr, Why new technology is more problematic than old technology. In: Bondeson, WB, Englehardt, HT Jr, Spicker, SF, White, JM Jr, Eds. New Knowledge in the Biomedical Sciences: Some Moral Implications of Its Acquisition, Possession, and Use. Dordrecht and Boston: D. Reidel Publishing Co., 1982:182 (emphasis added).Google Scholar

70. See note 18. Morreim, 1991:85.Google Scholar

71. Tong, R. Towards a just, courageous, and honest resolution of the futility debate. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 1995; 20(2): 187–88.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

72. Zaner, RM, Bliton, MJ. The injustice of it all: caring for the chronically ill. Journal of Clinical Ethics 1991;2(3):157–8.Google Scholar

73. Merleau-Ponty, M. Phenomenology of Perception. Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1962:354.Google Scholar