Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-jr42d Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-18T11:20:00.853Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A Dialogue on Species-Specific Rights: Humans and Animals in Bioethics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 July 2009

David C. Thomasma
Affiliation:
is the Fr. Michael I. English, S.J. Professor of Medical Ethics and Director of the Medical Humanities Program at Loyola University Chicago Medical Center.
Erich H. Loewy
Affiliation:
is Professor and Alumni Chair of Bioethics at the University of California, Davis.

Extract

At the end of the most violent century in human history, it is good to take stock of our commitments to human and other life forms, as well as to examine the rights and the duties that might flow from their biological makeup. Professor Thomasma and Professor Loewy have held a long-standing dialogue on whether there are moral differences between animals and humans. This dialogue was occasioned by a presentation Thomasma made some years ago at Loewy's invitation at the University of Illinois, Peoria, Medical Center. During that presentation, Thomasma argued that human beings are sufficiently distinct from other animals genetically and otherwise to justify a moral difference in rights and obligations. In effect, he argued that there are species-specific rights. This essay will pick up the threads of that dialogue.

Type
Special Section: Expanding the Boundaries of Bioethics
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1997

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1. Although a study in England has suggested that over 20% of those diagnosed with PVS have been able later to convey at least simple statements about their previous condition, suggesting that they maintain some conscious awareness of being trapped in that state. As Ron Cranford suggests, they may suffer more than we are aware they do. See: Los Angeles Times News Service. Beliefs on vegetative state are challenged: British study raises questions about doctors' ability to assess faculties of the terminally ill. Des Moines Sunday Register, 07 7, 1996:2.Google Scholar

2. Jain, R, Thomasma, DC. Discontinuing life support in an infant of a drug-addicted mother: Whose decision is it? Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 1997;6:4854.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

3. Thomasma, DC. Abstract medical knowledge, newborns, and uncertainty: a challenge to philosophy of medicine. In: Goldworth, A, Silverman, W, Stevenson, D, AND Yoma, E, eds. Ethics and Perinatology, New York: Oxford University Press, 1991:146–61.Google Scholar

4. Anonymous. Frozen embryos to be destroyed. Chicago Sun-Times, 1996;July 8:22.Google Scholar

5. Catholic, Church. Instruction on Respect for Human Life in its Origin and on the Dignity of Procreation. Vatican City: The Congregation, 1987.Google Scholar

6. Ashley, B, Moraczewski, AS. Is the biological subject of human rights present from conception? In: Cataldo, PJ, Moraczewski, AS, eds. The Fetal Tissue Issues: Medical and Ethical Aspects. Braintree (MA): The Pope John Center, 1994:3360.Google Scholar

7. Diamond, J. Why women change. Discover: The World of Science 1996;17(7):131–7.Google Scholar

8. See, among others, De Waal, F. Good Matured: The Origins of Right and Wrong in Human and Other Animals. Cambridge (MA): Harvard University Press, 1996;Google Scholar and Sorabji, R: Animal Minds and Human Morals. New York: Cornell University Press, 1993.Google Scholar

9. That higher animals have a sense of compassion was one of the points made by Rousseau (See: Rousseau, JJ. Le Contrat Social. Grimsley, R, ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1972),Google Scholar as well as by Darwin, who points out that compassion has distinct survival value (See: Darwin, C. The Descent of Man. New York: H.M. Caldwell, 1874).Google Scholar Schopenhauer, among others, considered compassion to be the driving force (”Triebfeder” ) of ethics (See: Schopenhauer, A. Preisschrift iiber die Grundlage der Moral. In: Arthur Schopenhauer, Samtliche Werke, Band III. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1986)Google Scholar. A discussion of the role of compassion can be found in Loewy, EH: Freedom and Community: The Ethics of Interdependence. Albany (NY): SUNY Press, 1993.Google Scholar

10. Bentham in passing makes the point that it is not the capacity to reason but the capacity to suffer that is ethically of primary significance. See: Bentham, J. The Principles of Morals and Legislation. New York: Hafner, 1948.Google Scholar

11. Rachels, J: Created from Animals: The Moral Implication of Darwinism. New York: Oxford University Press, 1990.Google Scholar

12. Merriam Webster's Collegiate Dictionary, s.v. “species'