Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-wq2xx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-23T08:57:02.774Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Introduction: Thought as Language

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 April 2010

Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Extract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

Western philosophy has a long-standing interest in the relationship between thought and language. This is not least because language use and our mental capacities are so central to our human self-conception, as well as to the ways in which we have tried to think about other beings. Retrospectively, it is possible to identify certain broad traditions in the philosophical study of thought and language, traditions which also have their representatives in psychology and linguistics. In this introduction I shall focus on one such tradition, the one sometimes known as ‘lingualism ’, in so far as it bears on the papers brought together in this volume.

Type
Papers
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 1997

References

Referances

Davidson, D. 1982. ‘Rational Animals’, Dialectica 36, 317-27. Reprinted i n E. Lepore and B. McLaughlin (eds), Actions and Events: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson. Oxford: Blackwell, 1984Google Scholar
Fodor, J. 1975. The Language of Thought. Cambridge MA: Harvard University PressGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. 1981. Representations: Philosophical Essays on the Foundations Cognitive Science. Sussex: Harvester PressGoogle Scholar
Frege G. 1918. ‘The Thought: A Logical Inquiry’. Reprinted in P. F. Strawson (ed.), Philosophical Logic. Oxford University Press, 1967Google Scholar
Hacker, P. M. S. 1993. Wittgenstein: Meaning and Mind, Part I: Essays. Oxford: BlackwellGoogle Scholar
James, W. 1890. Principles of Psychology. Reprinted, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1981Google Scholar
Leibniz, G. 1677. Dialogue on the Connection between Things and Words Reprinted in P. P. Weiner (ed.), Leibniz Selections (New York: Scribners, 1951).Google Scholar
McGinn, C. 1982. The Character of Mind. Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Russell, B. A. W. 1956. ‘The Philosophy of Logical Atomism’ (1919). Reprinted in Logic and Knowledge. London: Allen & UnwinGoogle Scholar
Watson, J. B. 1919. Psychology from the Standpoint of a Behaviorist. Philadelphia: J. B. LippincottCrossRefGoogle Scholar
White, A. R. 1972. ‘What We Believe’, in Rescher, N. (ed.), Studies in the Philosophy of Mind: American Philosophical Quarterly Monograph Series, No. 6. Oxford: BlackwellGoogle Scholar
White, A. R. 1979. ‘Belief as a Propositional Attitude’, in Roberts, G. W (ed.), Bertrand Russell Memorial Volume. London: Allen & UnwinGoogle Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1979. Notebooks, 1914–1916, 2nd edition. Oxford: BlackwellGoogle Scholar