Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-m8qmq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-20T01:56:52.241Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Quality, Thought and Consciousness

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  07 July 2010

Howard Robinson
Affiliation:
Central European University, Budapest

Abstract

My objective in this essay is to argue for two things. The first is that intellectual mental states – thoughts – are not physicalistically reducible, just as qualia are not reducible. The second is that thoughts and qualia are not as different as is sometimes believed, but not because – as some empiricists thought – thoughts are qualia-like by being mental images, but because qualia are universals and their apprehension is a proto-intellectual act. I shall mainly be concerned with the first of these topics.

Type
Papers
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 As others have remarked, this is an eccentric use of ‘syntactic’, for syntax is hardly more of a physical feature of sentences than is semantics. The point of the metaphor (if that is what it is) is that a computing machine works because shapes fit holes, not because meanings fit anything.

2 This idea is passim, at least in Dennett's early work, such as Brainstorms (Hassocks: Harvester, 1978) and The Intentional Stance (Cambridge Mass.: MIT Press, 1987). One might cite in particular ‘Three Kinds of Intentional Psychology’ in R. Healey (ed.), Reduction, Time and Reality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), reprinted in The Intentional Stance.

3 Seager, W., ‘Real Patterns and Surface Metaphysics’ in Ross, D., Brook, A. and Thompson, D., Dennett's Philosophy: A Comprehensive Assessment (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 2000), 95129Google Scholar: 117.

5 Ibid., 121.

6 D. Dennett, ‘With a Little Help from My Friends’ in D. Ross, A. Brook and D. Thompson (eds), Dennett's Philosophy: A Comprehensive Assessment, op. cit., 327–88: 355.

7 Ibid.

8 Robinson, H., ‘Dualism’ in The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Mind, edited by Stitch, S. and Warfield, T. A. (Oxford: Blackwell, 2009), 85101Google Scholar; Robinson, H., ‘Reductionism, Supervenience and Emergence’ in The Routledge Companion to Metaphysics, edited by Simons, P. and Le Poidevin, R. (London: Routledge, 2009), 527–36Google Scholar.

9 Carnap, R., The Unity of Science (London: Kegan Paul, 1934)Google Scholar.

10 Nagel, E., The Structure of Science (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1961)Google Scholar.

11 Ayer, A. J., The Origins of Pragmatism (London: Macmillan, 1968)Google Scholar; Jackson, F., ‘Epiphenomenal Qualia’, Philosophical Quarterly 32 (1982), 127–36Google Scholar; Chalmers, D., The Conscious Mind (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996)Google Scholar; Russell, B., The Analysis of Matter (London: Allen and Unwin, 1927)Google Scholar.

12 Kripke, S., Wittgenstein and Rule-Following (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1976)Google Scholar; Putnam, H., ‘Brains in a Vat’ in his Reason, Truth and History (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), 121Google Scholar.

13 I am grateful to the participants at the Metaphysics of Consciousness conference in Edinburgh in July 2009 and to Anita Avramides and Adrian Moore who commented on a later version of the paper.