Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-qsmjn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-19T03:28:58.010Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

What do Religious Believers Believe?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  20 June 2011

Richard Norman
Affiliation:
University of Kent

Extract

A common response to Richard Dawkins' assault on religious belief has been that he is attacking a straw man. The beliefs of religious believers, so the protest goes, are not as crude and simplistic as the ones which he attributes to them. Here is Terry Eagleton's comment to that effect:

Imagine someone holding forth on biology whose only knowledge of the subject is the Book of British Birds, and you have a rough idea of what it feels like to read Richard Dawkins on theology. Card-carrying rationalists like Dawkins…invariably come up with vulgar caricatures of religious faith that would make a first-year theology student wince.

Type
Papers
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Terry Eagleton, ‘Lunging, Flailing, Mispunching’, London Review of Books 19 October 2006.

2 Swinburne, Richard, Is There a God? (Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 1996), 4CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

3 Some examples of this line of argument are: Swinburne, Richard, The Existence of God (Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 1979)Google Scholar, and Is There a God?; Polkinghorne, John, Belief in God in an Age of Science (New Haven and London: Yale University Press, 1998)Google Scholar, Science and Theology (London: SPCK, 1998)Google Scholar, and many other works; Ward, Keith, Why There Almost Certainly Is a God (Oxford: Lion Hudson, 2008)Google Scholar.

4 Dawkins, Richard, The God Delusion (London: Bantam Press, 2006)Google Scholar, 134ff, esp. 109 and 148–150.

5 Eagleton, ‘Lunging, Flailing, Mispunching’.

6 Wittgenstein, Ludwig, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1922), 6.44Google Scholar.

7 I do not have space to discuss here other possible ways of providing a rational basis for belief in the existence of a personal deity, such as appeals to religious experience of the kind defended by Ward, (Why There Almost Certainly is a God, ch. 7). I say something about appeals to religious experience, and why I think they fail, in my On Humanism (London: Routledge, 2004), 41–2Google Scholar, and in ‘The Varieties of Non-Religious Experience’, in Cottingham, John (ed.), The Meaning of Theism (Oxford: Blackwell, 2007)Google Scholar.

8 Dawkins, The God Delusion, 306.

9 Milbank, John, ‘Postmodern Critical Augustinianism: A Short Summa in Forty-two Responses to Unasked Questions’, in Ward, Graham (ed.), The Postmodern God: a Theological Reader (Oxford: Blackwell, 1997), 265Google Scholar.

10 Cornwell, John, Darwin's Angel (London: Profile Books, 2007), 4344Google Scholar.

11 Lindbeck, George A., The Nature of Doctrine (Louisville: Westminster John Knox Press, 1984)Google Scholar.

12 Ibid., 68.

13 Lindbeck, The Nature of Doctrine, 48, 51.

14 Ibid., 94.

15 Cornwell, Darwin's Angel, 48.

16 Lucretius, De Rerum Natura, Book I, lines 1–5, in the translation by Latham, R. E., The Nature of the Universe (Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1951)Google Scholar.

17 Soskice, Janet, Metaphor and Religious Language (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1985), 95Google Scholar.

18 Cornwell, Darwin's Angel, 34–5.

19 Braithwaite, Richard, ‘An Empiricist's View of the Nature of Religious Belief’, in Mitchell, Basil (ed.), The Philosophy of Religion (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1971), 82Google Scholar.

20 Ibid., 84.

22 Lash, Nicholas, ‘Where Does The God Delusion Come From?’, in Theology for Pilgrims (London: Darton, Longman and Todd, 2008), 7Google Scholar.

24 Ibid., 8–9.